4 Introduction
Put very briefly, I take Hegel’s response to the demand that metaphysics should
be set aside, to be that in a very real sense, metaphysics is unavoidable:⁹ that is,
we cannot escape making metaphysical assumptions in everything we believe, in
how we act, and in how we live our lives and relate to the things around us. Thus,
if we take metaphysics to be concerned with our fundamental view of ourselves
and the world of which we are part, of its basic n ature and structure, we cannot
help subscribing to some such metaphysics, so that speculation on this matter is
inescapable, and anyone who thinks he does not have a metaphysical position,
or can opt out of having one, is deluding himself.¹⁰
One way of trying to avoid this conclusion might be to claim that we can
form views about the world within the natural sciences in a way that is somehow
distinct from metaphysics, in the spirit of Newton’s ‘hypotheses non fingo’.
Hegel, however, is scornful of such manoeuvres:
It is true that Newton expressly warned physics to beware of metaphysics; but to his
honour, let it be said that he did not conduct himself in accordance with this warning at
all. Only the animals are true blue physicists by this standard, since they do not think;
whereas humans, in contrast, are thinking beings, and born metaphysicians.¹¹
Another response might be to just stick to ‘common sense’, treating this as a form
of thinking somehow prior to and independent of metaphysical speculations and
assumptions. But again, Hegel denies that there can be any such standpoint,
even though our preoccupation with our daily affairs may lead us to overlook or
ignore the metaphysical dimension and take it for granted:
[E]veryone possesses and uses the wholly abstract category of being.Thesunis in the
sky; these grapes are ripe, and so on ad infinitum. Or, in a higher sphere of education,
we proceed to the relation of cause and effect, force and its manifestation, etc. All our
knowledge and ideas are entwined with metaphysics like this and governed by it; it is the
⁹ In a way, of course, Kant thought something similar: but as we shall see, Hegel’s take on the
unavoidability of metaphysics is importantly different from—and more optimistic than—Kant’s.
Cf. Kant’s remarks about what he calls ‘indifferentism’, CPR Ax–xi.
¹⁰ For a similar view in the contemporary literature, see E. J. Lowe, The Possibility of Metaphysics:
Substance, Identity, and Time (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), v: ‘In my view, all other forms
of inquiry rest upon metaphysical presuppositions—thus making metaphysics unavoidable—so
that we should at least endeavour to do metaphys ics with our eyes open, rather than allowing it to
exercise its influence upon us at the level of uncritical assumption’.
¹¹ EL, §98Z, 156 [Werke, VIII: 207]. Hegel makes a similar comment with reference to
Newton in a letter to Goethe, 24 February 1821: see Hegel: The Letters, trans. Clark Butler and
Christiane Seiler (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1984), 700. Cf. also EL, §38, 77–8: ‘The
fundamental illusion in scientific empiricism is always that it uses the metaphysical categories of
matter, force, as well as those of one, many, universality, and the infinite, etc., and it goes on to draw
conclusions, guided by categories of this sort, presupposing and applying the forms of syllogising in
the process. It does all this without knowing that it thereby itself contains a metaphysics and is
engaged in it, and that it is using those categories and their connections in a totally uncritical and
unconscious manner’. Again, Hegel’s view here chimes with that of contemporary positions, such
as Lowe’s: ‘Scientists inevitably make metaphysical assumptions, whether explicitly or implicitly,
in proposing and testing their theories—assumptions which go beyond anything that science itself
can legitimate’ (Lowe, The Possibility of Metaphysics,5).