28 Introduction
merely shift the difficulty from grasping the necessary structure of reality to the
necessary structure of our experience. Moreover, as we shall see in more detail
in the papers that follow, while I believe Hegel’s response to Kant does commit
him to a realism about universals and thus to a form of conceptual realism,
defined as ‘the belief that concepts are part of the structure of reality’,⁶⁷ different
varieties of such realism are possible; Hegel, I argue, tries to avoid the sort of
extreme Platonism that might force him to adopt an excessively rationalistic
epistemology,⁶⁸ and instead adopts a more broadly Aristotelian approach, which
allows him to work within an epistemology that can accommodate elements of
empiricism as well as rationalism,⁶⁹ just as Kant himself claimed to do.
A second difficulty facing the Hegelian project is not the epistemological
price that it might have to pay, but in the end whether it does any better than
the Kantian story in explaining the puzzling phenomena with which both are
concerned. For, just as it has been argued against realist accounts of natural
⁶⁷ Michael Rosen, ‘From Vorstellung to Thought: Is a ‘‘Non-Metaphysical’’ View of Hegel
Possible?’, in Dieter Henrich and Rolf-Peter Horstmann (eds.), Metaphysik nach Kant? (Stuttgart:
Klett-Cotta, 1988), 248–62, at 262; repr. in Robert Stern (ed.), G. W. F. Hegel: Critical Assessments,
4 vols (London: Routledge, 1993), III, 329–44, at 343.
⁶⁸ Cf. LHP II, 29 [Werke, XIX: 39]: ‘Through his presentation of his Ideas, Plato opened up
the intellectual world, which, however, is not beyond reality, in heaven, in another place, but is
the real world’. Cf. EL, §12, 37 [Werke, VIII, 57]: ‘When thinking stops at the universality of the
ideas—as was necessarily the case with the first philosophies (for instance, with the Being of the
Eleatic school, the Becoming of Heraclitus, and so on)—then it is rightly accused of formalism.It
can happen, even in a developed philosophy [where of course Hegel has Schelling in mind], that
only abstract principles or determinations are apprehended (for instance, ‘‘That in the Absolute all is
one,’’ ‘‘The identity of the subjective and the objective’’), and that with regard to what is particular
these same determinations are simply repeated. With reference to the first abstract universality of
thinking, there is a correct and more fundamental sense in which the development of philosophy is
due to experience’. These passages, along with many others, show why it is too simplistic to accuse
Hegel of simply adopting a form of ‘intellectual intuition’ as the basis for his epistemology, in the
way that Kantians are inclined to do, and thus to argue that Hegel rejected ‘the need for reception
of information about the particulars of nature as well as conceptualization’ (Paul Guyer, ‘Thought
and Being: Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Theoretical Philosophy’, in Frederick C. Beiser (ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 171–210, at
203)—the question, rather, is exactly what this ‘information’ contains, and how much we can get
from it. Cf. Oderberg, Real Essentialism, 23–5.
⁶⁹ So, for example, while he disputes the empiricists’ limited account of what can be known
through experience, Hegel does not deny the significance of experience itself as giving us the capacity
to grasp the more general principles governing the behaviour of the phenomena. Cf. EL, §24Z,
60 [Werke, VIII: 87]: ‘A great mind has great experiences, and in the motley play of appearance
spots the crucial point. The Idea is present and actual, not something over the h ills and far away. A
great mind, the mind of a Goethe, for instance, when it looks into nature and history; it sees what
is rational and expresses it. Furthermore, we can also become cognizant of what is true through
reflection; we are then determining it through relationships to thought’; and LHP III, 444–5
[Werke, XX: 352], where Hegel claims that ‘experience and observation of the world mean nothing
else for Kant than a candlestick standing here, and a snuff-box standing there’, where he makes plain
that he considers Kant to thereby have an inadequate conception of what experience can amount
to, which in turn makes the problem of grasping general principles and laws more intractable.
Hegel discusses the relation between experience and thought extensively in the Introduction to EL,
§§1–18, 24–42 [Werke, VIII: 41–64].