Hegel and Pragmatism 221
Indeed, this fear [of error] takes something—a great deal in fact—for granted as truth,
supporting its scruples and inferences on what is itself in need of prior scrutiny to see if it
is true. To be specific, it takes for granted certain ideas about cognition as an instrument
and as a medium, and assumes that there is a difference between ourselves and this cognition.
Above all, it presupposes that the Absolute stands on one side and cognition on the
other, independent and separated from it, and yet is something real; or in other words, it
presupposes that cognition which, since it is excluded from the Absolute, is surely outside
of the truth as well, is nevertheless true, an assumption whereby what calls itself fear of
error reveals itself rather as fear of truth.³²
Thus, while it may claim to be the most rational procedure because it is without
presuppositions, Hegel argues that the critical approach is not, and makes no
fewer presuppositions than the sort of position that just ‘gets on with the work
itself’, rather than tarrying on the brink.³³
³² Hegel, PS,47[Werke III: 69–70].
³³ Houlgate, I think, would want to put the Hegelian position even more strongly than this. On
my reading, Hegel’s point is that at the outset of any inquiry, in some ways both he and the critical
philosopher are taking something for granted (the Hegelian, that our cognitive capacities are capable
of taking us to the truth, so that these inquiries are worth s tarting; the critical philosopher that our
faculties stand between us and the world, so require investigation before we can trust them); but
the Hegelian approach is to be preferred because that way we at least stand some chance of actually
getting at the truth because we will begin inquiring, whereas on the critical approach we will just
get stuck in a paralysing self-doubt. The point about presuppositions, then, is the relatively weak
one, that if we thought that the critical approach is nonetheless the one to be preferred because it
involves no assumptions, this would be a spurious preference because (Hegel claims) in fact both
sides are on a par on this issue. Houlgate, however, thinks that Hegel is not just arguing that
neither side can use the point about presuppositions in its support; rather he thinks Hegel is arguing
that his position is presuppositionless in a way that the critical position is not, so that this tells
in its favour. Houlgate’s grounds for this seem to be that if we attempt to think in an altogether
presuppositionless way, we will not only abandon the belief that thought and being are distinct
because we will see that this rests on certain assumptions; having let go of any assumptions, we
will come to see that if we really want to think presuppositionlessly, we must think that they are
one. But, my worry here is that from the fact that accepting one position involves making some
assumptions, it does not follow that accepting its opposite involves making none. Cf. Houlgate,
Introduction to Hegel, 44–5: ‘Hegel’s claim is not that being is a mere postulate of thought [i.e. that
we may legitimately assume that thought and being coincide]. On the contrary, he argues that, for
the fully self-critical philosopher who suspends all his determinate preconceptions about thought
and being, our thought of being cannot be anything less than the thought of being itself. Thought
cannot be assumed necessarily to fall short of what there is—to be confined, for example, to the
realm of conceivable possibility—but must be understood to be the awareness and disclosure of
being as such. This may seem to some to be presumptuous. How can thought be certain that it is
able to bridge the gap between itself and being and disclose the true nature of what there is? From
the point of view of the self-critical philosopher, however, this question is illegitimate, for we are not
entitled to presuppose that there is such a gap in the first place. The fully self-critical philosopher
may not assume that being is anything beyond what thought itself is aware of. Consequently, he or
she may not assume that thought is aware of anything less than being itself’. (Cf. also Houlgate,
Hegel’s ‘Logic’, 130.) Houlgate might be right that the philosopher who is ‘fully self-critical’, and
who thus wants to think making no assumptions whatsoever, will not feel entitled to believe that
there is a gap between thought and being, because he will see that this requires us to make certain
presuppositions about the nature of thought and being; but even if this is so, from this it doesn’t
follow that the fully self-critical philosopher who is attempting to think presuppositionlessly will
therefore see that he can start without any assumptions if he believes there is no such gap; rather,