138 British Hegelianism: A Non-Metaphysical View?
McTaggart’s argument here is this: There are some categories that it is legitimate to
employ in thinking about things within the universe, that we cannot legitimately
employ in thinking about the universe as a whole. Thus, although everything
within the universe can be thought to have a cause, this concept cannot be
applied to the universe as a totality: for, in order for something to have a cause,
there must be something outside it, of which it is the effect, but this cannot be
true of the totality of things, which cannot (ex hypothesi) have anything beyond
itself to act as a cause. It can therefore be meaningful to ask only of events or
things within the universe why they have occurred or why they exist: it cannot
be meaningful to ask this of the universe as a whole.⁵⁷ In this way, it appears,
the question of existence is unanswerable because it goes beyond the point at
which the search for reasons makes sense, and as such the rationalist is in no way
obliged to respond to it.
Now, in adopting this approach, McTaggart can once again be seen to have
turned the tables on Hegel’s nineteenth-century critics. As we have seen, they
had argued that in a vain effort to overcome the question of existence, Hegel had
sought to derive the being of the universe from its essence, and so to treat the
Logic as a kind of first cause. On McTaggart’s reading, however, Hegel’s position
is no longer taken to involve any such claim: instead, McTaggart argues that it
was through categorical analysis alone that Hegel had wanted to show that the
question lacks any real content, ‘for it is the application of a category, which has
only meaning within the universe, to the universe as a whole’. ⁵⁸
This attempt by McTaggart to defuse the question of existence could of
course be challenged. Perhaps the main difficulty is that while it might show
that it is wrong to ask for a causal explanation for the existence of the universe,
strategy is used by both Ritchie and Seth (in one of his earlier, pro-Hegelian writings): see D. G.
Ritchie, ‘What is Reality?’, Philosophical Review, 1 (1892), 265–83, at 277–8, and Seth, ‘Philosophy
as Criticism of Categories’, 39–40.
⁵⁷ Versions of this position are often used to attack the Cosmological Argument, which argues
from the existence of the universe to a transcendent cause. Cf. Ronald Hepburn, Christianity and
Paradox (London: Watts, 1958), 167–8 and William Rowe, The Cosmological Argument (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1975), 132 ff.
⁵⁸ Cf. McTaggart, ‘The Changes of Method in Hegel’s Dialectic’, 205; repr. in Stern (ed.),
Critical Assessments,vol.2,88:
The dialectical system is not so wonderful or mystic as it has been represented to be. It makes
no attempt to deduce existence from essence; it does not even attempt to eliminate the element
of immediacy in experience, and to produce a self-sufficient and self-mediating thought. It cannot
even, if the view I have taken is right, claim that its course is a perfect mirror of the nature of reality.
But although the results which it attains are comparatively commonplace, they go as far as we can
for any practical purpose desire. For, if we accept the system, we learn from it that in the universe
is realised the whole of reason, and nothing but reason. Contingency, in that sense in which it is
baffling and oppressive to our minds, has disappeared. For it would be possible, according to this
theory, to prove that the only contingent thing about the universe was its existence as a whole,
and this is not contingent in the ordinary sense of the word. Hegel’s philosophy is thus capable of
satisfying the needs, theoretical and practical, to satisfy which philosophy originally arose, nor is
there any reason to suppose that he ever wished it to do more.