British Hegelianism: A Non-Metaphysical View? 119
In the interpretation that Russell offers here, it is clear that many of the views
which currently would be dismissed as misreadings of Hegel may in fact be
better attributed to the British Hegelians, so that their attempt to appropriate
his metaphysics seems just to have had a distorting effect, and a detrimental
impact on the proper understanding of his work. In claiming that Hegel was
a mystic, who believed that all of reality formed a complex system, who did
not believe in the actuality of space and time, who thought that ‘whatever is,
is right’, and that there is a spiritual Absolute, many would now argue that
Russell was mistaken—in fact, only the British Hegelians held these views, and
such was their impact on the reception of Hegel in Britain, that only recently
has a picture of his thought developed here that is free of their pernicious
influence.
In view of this, it therefore seems clear that there is unlikely to be much in
common between the more progressive contemporary views of Hegel, and those
of the British Hegelians, so there can be little hope of relating their conception
of Hegel to our own. For, whereas they are generally associated with one of
the most speculative episodes in Hegel’s Wirkungsgeschichte, an important strand
of contemporary scholarship has tried to distance Hegel himself from any such
metaphysical extravagances, offering instead a non-metaphysical reading of his
thought that is consciously critical of this sort of approach. This non-metaphysical
reading is not without its ambiguities, but its central claims have been helpfully
summarized by Michael Rosen as follows:
As I see it, ‘non-metaphysical’ interpretations of Hegel share two essential features. First,
as regards the content of Hegel’s system, the ‘non-metaphysical’ interpretation claims
that Hegel does not attempt to deal with objects beyond the range of sensible experience.
Second, as regards its method, the ‘non-metaphysical’ interpretation denies that Hegel’s
philosophy is a prioristic in the sense that Kant attacks dogmatic metaphysics for being a
prioristic.⁴
Thus, leaving aside complications of emphasis and detail, the main aim of
the non-metaphysical conception (to be found in the work of J. N. Findlay,
Klaus Hartmann, Alan White, Terry Pinkard, and others)⁵ is to get away from
⁴ Michael Rosen, ‘From Vorstellung to Thought: Is a ‘‘Non-Metaphysical’’ View of Hegel
Possible?’, in Dieter Henrich and Rolf-Peter Horstmann (eds.), Metaphysik nach Kant? (Stuttgart:
Klett-Cotta, 1988), 248–62, at 255; reprinted in Robert Stern (ed.), G. W. F. Hegel: Critical
Assessments, 4 vols. (London: Routledge, 1993), III, 329–44, at 335.
⁵ J. N. Findlay, Hegel: A Re-examination (New York: Collier Books, 1962); Klaus Hartmann,
‘Hegel: A Non-Metaphysical View’, in Alasdair MacIntyre (ed.), Hegel: A Collection of Critical
Essays (Garden City: Doubleday, 1972), 101–24; Alan White, Absolute Knowledge: Hegel and the
Problem of Metaphysics (Athens: Ohio University Press, 1983); Terry Pinkard, Hegel’s Dialectic:
The Explanation of Possibility (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1988). For a useful overview
of the place of this non-metaphysical conception in the tradition of Hegel-interpretation, see
Thomas E. Wartenberg, ‘Hegel’s Idealism: The Logic of Conceptuality’, in Frederick. C. Beiser
(ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993),
102–29.