Ridling, Philosophy Then and Now: A Look Back at 26 Centuries of Thought
884
However strange his doctrine may initially sound, Berkeley claimed that
he was merely describing the commonsense view of reality. To say that
colors, sounds, trees, dogs, and tables are ideas is not to say that they do not
really exist. It is merely to say what they are. To say that animals and pieces
of furniture are ideas is not to say that they are diaphanous, gossamer, and
evanescent. Opacity, density, and permanence are also ideas that partially
constitute these objects.
Berkeley has a syllogistic argument for his main point: physical things,
such as trees, dogs, and houses, are things perceived by sense, and things
perceived by sense are ideas; therefore, physical things are ideas. If one
objects that the first premise is false, Berkeley in reply would challenge the
objector to point out one example of something that is not sensed. The only
way to identify such an example is through some sensation, either by sight,
touch, taste, or hearing. In this way, any proffered counterexample becomes
an example of Berkeley’s point.
If one objects that the second premise of the syllogism is false on the
grounds that people sense things, not ideas, Berkeley would reply that there
are no sensations without ideas and that it makes no sense to speak of some
additional thing which ideas are supposed to represent or resemble. Unlike
Locke, Berkeley does not believe that there is anything “behind” ideas in a
world external to the mind. There could not be. If the alleged external objects,
of which ideas are supposed to be representations, exist, then they are
themselves either ideas or not. If they are ideas, then Berkeley’s point that
everything perceived is an idea is vindicated. If they are not ideas, then they
are unperceived; in particular, they would be invisible colors, intangible
textured things, odourless smells, and silent sounds. If someone objects that he
can imagine trees or books in a closet unperceived, Berkeley would reply that