Ridling, Philosophy Then and Now: A Look Back at 26 Centuries of Thought
823
why,” or “know whether.” These differences have been explored in detail,
especially in the 20th century. The expression “know x,” where “x” can be
replaced by a proper name, as in “I know Jones” or “He knows Rome,” has
been taken by some philosophers, notably Bertrand Russell (1872-1970), to be
a case of knowledge by acquaintance. Russell thought its characteristic use
was to express the kind of knowledge one has when one has first-hand
familiarity with a certain object, person, or place. Thus, one could not
properly say in the 20th century, “I know Julius Caesar,” since this would
imply that one had met or was directly acquainted with a person who had died
some 2,000 years ago. This sense or use of “know” becomes important in the
theory of perception and in sense-data theory, since some philosophers, such
as Russell and G.E. Moore (1873-1958), have held that one’s awareness of a
sense-datum (a notion to be discussed later) is a case of direct acquaintance,
whereas one’s acquaintance with a physical object, such as a human hand, is
not.
The phrases “know that” and “know how” have also played fundamental
roles in the theory of knowledge. The British philosopher Gilbert Ryle (1900-
76), for instance, argued that “know how” is normally used to refer to a kind
of skill that a person has, such as knowing how to swim. One could have such
knowledge without being able to explain to another what it is that one knows
in such a case, that is, without being able to convey to another the knowledge
required for that person to develop the same skill. “Know that,” in contrast,
does not seem to denote the possession of a skill or aptitude but rather the
possession of specific pieces of information, and the person who has
knowledge of this sort can generally convey it to others. To know that the
Concordat of Worms was signed in the year 1122 would be an example of this
sort of knowledge. Ryle has argued that, given these differences, some cases