Ridling, Philosophy Then and Now: A Look Back at 26 Centuries of Thought
361
still be an empirical concept if the occasion for its use were always his sense
experience of a blue object. Furthermore, the fact that men learn, postnatally,
to use the word cause does not prove that it expresses an empirical concept if
its application to something always implies more than the sense which
experience of that kind of thing presents to the mind.
Another supposedly identical but in fact more or less irrelevant property
of concepts and beliefs is that of the universality of their possession or
acceptance – that a priori or innate concepts must be the common possession
of all men and that such beliefs must be accepted by everyone. There may be,
in fact, some basis for inferring universality from innateness, since many
innate characteristics such as the fear of loud noises appear to be common to
the whole species.
Two main kinds of concept have been held to be a priori and thus
nonempirical. First, there are certain formal concepts of logic and of
mathematics that reflect the basic structure of discourse: “not,” “and,” “or,”
“if,” “all,” “some,” “existence,” “unity,” “number,” “successor,” “infinity,”
Secondly, there are categorial concepts, such as “substance,” “cause,” “mind,”
and “God,” so called after the “categories of thought” as listed by Aristotle
and Kant, which the mind imposes upon the given data of experience.
A very large variety of different types of proposition has been held to be
a priori. Few would deny this status to such definitional truisms or obvious
tautologies as “all hairless heads are bald” or “a rose is a rose.” There are also
the truths of logic, of mathematics, and of metaphysics – whether
transcendent, such as the existence of God or things-in-themselves (lying
behind appearances), or immanent and thus discernible within reality, such as
the principles (presupposed by much natural science) of conservation,