Ridling, Philosophy Then and Now: A Look Back at 26 Centuries of Thought
239
Modern Realism
In the familiar formula cogito ergo sum (“I think; therefore, I am”)
proffered by the first notable modern philosopher, René Descartes, methodical
thinking was rooted in thought itself, thus raising the problem of how any
material world outside of thought could be reached philosophically. In
Descartes and a half century later in the British Empiricist John Locke, an
external origin for sensations was accepted, though without any thoroughly
philosophical justification. Rather, the denial of an external world was
regarded as too absurd to be countenanced. In this perspective Locke’s
philosophy displayed a commonsense Realism. According to one of Locke’s
contemporaries, the Cartesian Nicolas Malebranche (known for his claim that
God’s will is the true cause of motion), religious faith guaranteed the external
world. The Cambridge Platonists, a sober group of 17th-century moral and
religious Rationalists, in a similar atmosphere of faith and with a Cartesian
understanding of sensation, acquiesced in the external existence of sensible
things while, against a Neoplatonic background, they accorded a respectively
greater reality to the objects of intellectual cognition. For Berkeley, an early
18th-century Empiricist and Idealist, the scriptural guarantee was lacking
because matter was nowhere mentioned in the revealed descriptions of the
sensible universe; accordingly, in his view, no sensible world outside
cognition was left. But in David Hume, whose teachings marked the climax of
the Empiricist movement, even the cognitive subject, or soul, vanished.
Facing the impossibility of a genuine philosophical justification for
arguing to an external world from the starting point of mind or idea, Claude
Buffier, an early 18th-century French Jesuit, and, shortly later, the Scottish
Realists leaned explicitly on common sense as the motive for accepting the
world’s external existence. The most prominent exponent of this school was