seau, Hume, Mill, and Marx—give very good, though not perhaps perfect,
answers to the questions that concern them. This is why we still read their
texts and find what they say instructive.
2. The criticisms I shall make do not consist in pointing out fallacies and
inconsistencies in, say, Locke’s or Mill’s thought, but rather in examining a
few basic respects in which we, from our own point of view and concerned
with our own questions or problems, do not find their answers or solutions
altogether acceptable, as instructive as they are. Therefore, when we discuss
these writers our first effort is to understand what they say, and to interpret
them in the best way their point of view seems to allow. Only then shall we
regard ourselves as ready to judge their solution from our point of view. I
believe that unless we follow these guidelines in reading the works of these
six philosophers, we fail to treat them as conscientious and intelligent writ-
ers who are in all essential respects at least our equals.
In taking up Locke
2
I shall consider but one main difficulty which arises
from the fact that, as described in the Second Treatise, Locke’s social con-
tract doctrine may justify or allow for inequalities in basic political rights
and liberties. For example, the right to vote is restricted by a property quali-
fication. The constitution he envisages is that of a class state: that is, politi-
[ 104 ]
locke
2. Useful secondary sources on Locke are: Richard Ashcraft, Revolutionary Politics and
Locke’s “Two Treatises of Government” (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986), and
Locke’s Two Treatises of Government (London: Unwin, 1987); Michael Ayres, Locke: Epistemol-
ogy-Ontology, 2 vols. (London: Routledge, 1991); Joshua Cohen, “Structure, Choice and Le-
gitimacy: Locke’s Theory of the State,” PAPA, Fall 1986; John Dunn, The Political Thought
of John Locke (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969); Julian Franklin, John Locke
and the Theory of Sovereignty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978); Ruth Grant,
John Locke’s Liberalism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987); Peter Laslett, Introduc-
tion to Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Student Edi-
tion, 1988); Wolfgang von Leyden, John Locke, Essays on the Law of Nature (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1954); C. B. MacPherson, Political Theory of Possessive Individualism (Ox-
ford: Oxford University Press, 1962); J. B. Schneewind, Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to
Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 2 vols., in Vol. 1, pp. 183–198; Peter
Schouls, The Imposition of Method: A Study of Descartes and Locke (New York: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1980); John Simmons, The Lockean Theory of Rights (Princeton: Princeton Univer-
sity Press, 1992), and On the Edge of Anarchy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993);
Richard Tuck, Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1979); James Tully, A Discourse on Property: John Locke and His Adversaries
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980); Jeremy Waldron, The Right to Private Prop-
erty (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), esp. Ch. 8, and “Locke, Toleration, and the Rational-
ity of Persecution,” in Liberal Rights: Collected Papers (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1993).
Copyright © The President and Fellows of Harvard College
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY