dog’ (or in ‘A dachshund is a dog’) the name ‘confused’ was given to the
supposition of the word ‘dog’. In confused supposition, as in distributive
supposition, it makes no sense to ask ‘Which dog?’ (SL 82).
All the kinds of supposition we have listed—simple supposition and the
various forms of personal supposition—are examples of ‘formal suppos-
ition’. Formal supposition, naturally enough, contrasts with material
supposition, and the underlying idea is that the sound of a word is its
matter, while its meaning is its form. The Latin equivalent of ‘ ‘‘Dog’’ is a
monosyllable’ would be an instance of material supposition, and so is the
equivalent of ‘ ‘‘dog’’ is a noun’. This is, in eVec t, the use of a word to refer
to itself, to talk about its symbolic properties rather than about what it
means or stands for. Once again, modern English speakers have the
advantage over medieval Latinists. In general it takes no philosophical
skill to identify material supposition, because from childhood we are
taught that when we are mentioning a word, rather than using it in the
normal way, we must employ quotation marks and write ‘ ‘‘dog’’ is a
monosyllable’. But in more complicated cases confusion between signs
and things signiWed continues to occ ur from time to time even in the
works of trained philosophers.8
Supposition was the most important semantic property of terms, but
there were others, too, recognized by medieval logicians. One was appella-
tion, which is connected with the scope of terms and sentences. Consider
the sentence ‘Dinosaurs have long tails’. Is this true, now that there are no
dinosaurs? If we take the view that a sentence is made true or false on the
basis of the current contents of the universe, then it seems that the
sentence cannot be true; and we cannot remedy this problem simply by
changing the tense of the verb to ‘had’. If we wish to regard the sentence as
true, we shall have to regard truth as something to be determined on the
basis of all the contents of the universe, past, present, and future. The
medievals posed this problem as being one about the appellation of the
term ‘dinosaur’.
8 The reader should be warned that though most logicians made the distinctions identiWed
above, there is considerable variation in the terminology used to make them. Moreover, in
the interests of simplicity I have abbreviated some of the technical terms. What I have
called ‘confused supposition’ should strictly be called ‘merely confused’ and what I have called
‘distributive’ should be called ‘confused and distributive’. See Paul Spade in CHLMP 196, and
W. Kneale, in The Development of Logic (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962), 252.
LOGIC AND LANGUAGE
131