Scepticism. He collected together sceptical arguments of the kind that we
have encountered in this chapter, and grouped them under ten headings,
which achieved fame as the Ten Tropes of Aenesidemus. Our knowledge of
them, a s of much else in ancient scepticism, derives from the writings of
Sextus Empiricus, a Pyrrhonian sceptic of the second century ad.
Sextus left three books of Outlines of Pyrrhonism and eleven books Against the
Professors. In these books appear almost all the sceptical arguments from
illusion that appeared in the later literature, and many that no one cared to
use again . We Wnd in him the yellow look of jaundice, the after-image on
the book, vision distorted by pressure on the eyeball, concave and convex
mirrors, wine which tastes sour after Wgs and sweet after nuts, ships
apparently stationary on the horizon, oars bent in water, smells more
pungent in the bathroom, the Xeeting Xashes of colour on the necks of
pigeons, and, of course, our old friend the tower that looks round from
afar and square close at hand.
Sextus’ own version of scepticism turns out not to be as diVerent from
Academic Scepticism as he would have us believe. Sceptics, without giving
assent to anything, still seem, for him, to be able to have views, not only
about perceptual matters of everyday life, but even on philosophical issues.
Sextus’ works are of value to us, not because they give a new turn to the
sceptical discussion, but because they are a treasury of information about
the reasoning of earlier and more original sceptics. He brought to an end
the sceptical tradition he chronicled.
The study of ancient epistemology can teach us much about the nature
of knowledge and the limits of scepticism. Several insights became part of
the patrimony of all future philosophy: knowledge can only be of what is
true; knowledge is only knowledge if it can appeal implicitly or explicitly to
some kind of support, whether from experience, reasoning, or some other
source; and one who claims knowledge must be resolute, excluding the
possibility of being rightly converted, at a later stage, to a diVerent view.
However, ancient epistemology is bedevilled by two diVerent but related
fallacies. Both of them are generated by a misunderstanding of the truth
that whatever is knowledge must be true. One of the fallacies haunts
classical epistemology, up to the time of Aristotle; the other fallacy haunts
Hellenistic and imperial epistemology.
The Wrst fallacy is this. ‘Whatever is knowledge must be true’ may be
interpreted in two ways.
176
EPISTEMOLOGY