place of a pint of wine is the inner surface of the Xask containing it—
provided the X ask is stationary. But suppose the Xask is in motion, on a
punt perhaps Xoating down a river? Then the wine will be moving too,
from place to place, and its place has to be given by specifying its position
relative to the motionless river banks (4. 5. 212b15). So too with a tree in a
stream, surrou nded by rushing water: its place is given by the unmoving
bed in which it is rooted.2
As is clear from these examples, for Aristotle a thing is not only in the
place deWned by its immediate container, but also in whatever contains that
container. Thus, just as a child may write out his address as 1 High Street,
Oxford, England, Europe, The Earth, The Universe, so Aristotle says, ‘You
are now in the universe because you are in the atmosphere and the
atmosphere is in the universe; and you are in the atmosphere because
you are on the earth, and you are on the earth because you are in your
own particular place.’ The universe is the place that is common to
everything.
If to be in place is to be within a container, it follows that the universe is
not in place at all: and this is a conclusion that Aristotle himself draws.
‘The universe is not anywhere; for whatever is somewhere must not only
exist itself, but also have something alongside it in which it is and which
contains it. But there is nothing outside the entire universe’ (Ph.4.5.
212b14–17). And if the universe is not in place, it cannot move from place
to place.
It is clear that place as described by Aristotle is quite diVerent from space
as often conceived since Newton as an in Wnite extension or cosmic grid.
Newtonian space would exist whether or not the material universe had
been created. For Aristotle, if there were no bodies there would be no place;
there can, however, be a vacuum, a place empty of bodies, but only if the
place is bounded by actual bodies (4. 1. 208b26). His concept of place,
therefore, can avoid the diYculties that have led philosophers such as
Kant to deny the reality of space. However, he adds to his basic concept a
signiWcant element that is irredeemably anachronistic: the notion of
natural place.
In an ordered cosmos, Aristotle believed, each of the four elements,
earth, air, Wre, and water, had a natural place, which exercised a causal
2 See W. D. Ross, Aristotle, 86; id., Aristotle’s Physics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1936), 575.
183
PHYSICS