German socialism and social democracy 1860–1900
We are not a parliamentary party, we do not send our deputies to the various represen-
tative bodies to parley – but also we are not makers of revolutions [Revolutionsmacher].
German Social Democracy is proud that its attitude is always to follow the principles
of its great master Marx, who would have nothing either of parliamentarism or of the
making of revolutions [Revolutionsmacherei]. We are a revolutionary party, our aim is a
revolutionary one, and we permit ourselves no illusions about its accomplishment by
parliamentary means. But we also know that the manner in which it will be achieved
does not depend upon us, that we cannot make the conditions under which we fight,
but that we have to study those conditions and we know that our task in conjunction
with this knowledge consists simply in acting in accord with what we know. (Lidtke
1966,p.153)
It is certainly a stunning statement: they sent deputies to parliament, but
were not a parliamentary party; they were revolutionaries, but did not
engage in revolution. Their task was to study conditions.
Marx and Engels had not been ambivalent when they wrote the Com-
munist Manifesto, but passionately called proletarians to revolution. Even
Lassalle, who also could lay some legitimate claim to being a revolutionary
in 1848–9, did not advise workers to use revolutionary force, but coun-
selled them to gain political power through the full use of the ballot and
parliament. By contrast, Marx and Engels spoke of ‘violent revolution’ that
would overthrow the bourgeoisie and of ‘sweeping away by force’ the old
relationships of production. They intended to incite fear, concluding that
‘the Communists...openly declare that their ends can be attained only
by the forcible overthrow of all existing social conditions. Let the ruling
classes tremble at a Communistic revolution. The proletarians have nothing
to lose but their chains. They have a world to win’ (Marx and Engels 1955,
i,pp.45, 54, 65). There is certainly no ambiguity in the Manifesto about the
need to use revolutionary force.
A political party, already under a legal ban, that hoped to avoid com-
plete suppression, could scarcely inscribe the rhetoric of the Manifesto in
its official programme without endangering its survival. The dilemma was
most troublesome for the radical wing of the party. One solution was to
remove violence and force from their definition of revolution. As early as
1871, Wilhelm Liebknecht set forth a view, not new with him, that stressed
the pervasiveness and gradualism of revolution. ‘All of human history’, he
said, ‘is a continuous revolution. History is the revolution in permanence –
it is becomingness, growth, change, progress – perpetual transformation,
because life is perpetual creation. As long as a human lives, he is a revo-
lutionary . . . The revolution, movement is life – the non-revolution, stasis
is death.’ This sounds mild, and it is, but Liebknecht wanted also to take
799