Aesthetics and politics
condition, but a process of constant renewal, with invigorating effects on
ethical life. It is order as produced, not given; but produced by free play, not
under duress. Stressing the importance of subjective assent and collaboration,
this idea also stands in opposition to the uniformity and identity of earlier
republican thought, permitting a more complex account of the general will.
According to Schiller’s aesthetic republicanism, ‘Man must learn to desire
more nobly, so that he may not need to will sublimely’ (Schiller 1967, Letter
XXIII. 8). It is not necessary to repress the particular identity, as sublime,
rigoristic versions of republicanism will demand (Moggach 2003,ch.7);
nor may it count as immediately valid, as in juridical accommodations
among existing particular interests (e.g. Kant’s population of intelligent
devils; Kant, 1991b, pp. 112–13). Instead, the particular self provides material
for aesthetic refashioning, a spontaneously generated self-transformation.
Aesthetic education elicits the idea of freedom in those who undertake it.
While art is independent from direct moral instruction, it acts like morality
in exemplifying freedom (Becq 1984, ii,p.848;Beiser2003,p.42). Schiller’s
position has been described not as art for art’s sake, but ‘art for life’s sake’
(Wilkinson and Willoughby 1967, p. clxxxi), enhancing individual and
collective existence. Through aesthetic education, the empirical individual
can correspond to the rational idea of Man, not because the ideal suppresses
the empirical self, but because individuals adapt and elevate themselves to the
stature of the idea (Schiller 1967, Letter IV. 2). The result is not uniformity,
but harmony (Schiller 1967, Letter XIII), not a one-sided subordination and
persistent internal division, but a mutual exchange and active reciprocity.
This unity-in-difference designates the aesthetic condition.
Schiller proposes two concepts of freedom, corresponding to the
Kantian beautiful and sublime. First, he sketches a beautiful concordance of
the faculties of mind (will, understanding and sensibility) within the individ-
ual personality, implying, further, harmony with external nature and with
other subjects. Aesthetic education is a process of self-formation, taming
disruptive passions and controlling them, not by repressive intellect, but by
cultivated taste, which can unobtrusively regulate social interactions. Sec-
ondly, he understands freedom as dignity, the sublime elevation of the self
above natural causality in the determination of ends. The compatibility of
these two conceptions, and Schiller’s success in integrating them, have been
disputed (Sharpe 1995,pp.47–8, 63–4), but his extensions and applications
of Kant were enormously influential. They depict aesthetic and political
self-determination and moral autonomy as the fulfilment of the idea of
spontaneity, not as its denial.
493