Aesthetics and politics
moral conscience, gain acknowledgement as the perquisites of the modern
subject. But, according to Hegel, to witness only this unfolding partic-
ularity is to have a one-sided vision, to miss the reflexive turn. Modern
solidarities are also constituted by acts of freedom and recognition, which
express the new understanding of the self (Hegel 1991,pp.282–3). Reflec-
tion here assumes the sense of reconnecting the multiple into a unity, not
forcibly, but in mutual affirmation.
4
This prospect is afforded by political
institutions in which subjects appear as an amplification, and not only as a
limitation, of one another’s freedom. For Hegel, the rational state, towards
which modernity tends, combines spontaneity or freedom with autonomy
or self-legislation consistent with this underlying diversity.
5
This mutual-
ity is prefigured in aesthetics, and even if, in Hegel’s mature thought, art
can no longer secure a genuine reconciliation among modern subjects, the
background of his theory of shared ethical life is provided in aesthetic ideas
of reflection deriving from Enlightenment sources.
Yet Hegel also describes modernity as a culture of rigid opposition,
fragmentation or diremption (Hegel 1964,pp.88, 90–1), an assertion of
unbridled particularity, which dangerously undermines the potentiality for
rational autonomy. In this image, the expansive and the reflexive motions
of modern subjectivity do not harmonise with each other. They remain in
stubborn opposition, and any momentarily achieved unity is highly fragile.
The centrifugal forces threaten constantly to overwhelm the integrative
capacities of modern institutions and relations. This image is one of mutual
antagonism and separation, between understanding and sensibility, freedom
and form, subject and subject, subject and object.
6
Hegel finds evidence of
these intractable contradictions in the philosophy of Kant, who nonetheless
struggled to resolve them, and in his own romantic contemporaries,
7
whom
he saw as irresponsibly extolling the tensions and conflicts of the modern
world. After Hegel, the ideal of rational self-determination is increasingly
4 Reflection will assume several different meanings in the authors examined here: the movement
from division towards unity (Hegel); the projection of a subjective content into objective existence
(expressivism); and, conversely, the withdrawal of the subject from external objects back into the self
(irony). This ambiguity is unavoidable; it is present in the texts under discussion, and illustrates the
central role played by reflection in this body of thought. In each case, the specific meaning will be
indicated.
5 For various recent per spectives on these issues, see Siep 1997.
6 Bernstein 1992,pp.1–65, sees in aesthetic theory a nostalgia for lost unity, but overstates the separation
between aesthetics, ethics and scientific reason by the time of Kant.
7 Hegel 1964 uses the term ‘romantic’ to designate post-classical, Christian ideas of the subject generally,
while stressing the new forms emerging from the Enlightenment. On various current definitions of
romanticism, see Butler 1981,pp.3–10.
483