K. Steven Vincent
argued that ‘all that which is the material of legislation and of politics is
an object of science, not opinion . . . Justice and legality are two things as
independent of our assent as mathematical truth’ (Beecher 1986,p.497;
Proudhon 1926a, p. 45). Brousse summarised his analytic method in typical
nineteenth-century terms: ‘to impartially reunify the facts, to deduce from
them a general law which permits the future to be foreseen’. He referred to
anarchism as ‘a scientifically constituted society’ (quoted in Stafford 1971,
pp. 61, 78).
Such beliefs in ‘science’ were common throughout the century, though
the scientific model from which social science was extrapolated changed
in the late nineteenth century, as Darwinian and evolutionary theories
replaced the more static imagery associated with Newtonian mechanics,
physiology and mathematics. Reclus, for example, who was a professional
geographer, believed that the progressive evolution of humanity was based
on ‘laws’ which could be discovered through observation – laws like solidar-
ity and brotherhood, which were destined to burst through current insti-
tutional restraints (including state-imposed ‘laws’ which, Reclus insisted,
violated the laws immanent in human nature). Kropotkin and Grave, also
reflecting the influence of evolutionary theory, argued that anarchism con-
formed to the physiological and psychological nature of man and therefore
enjoyed the stature of scientific truth. ‘Anarchy,’ Grave wrote in 1899, ‘is
a theory suppor ting itself on rational bases.’ Anarchists are distinctive, he
claimed, because they support themselves ‘on their observations, [and] they
deduce logical, natural laws for the organisation of a better society’ (Grave
1899,pp.2–3).
4
The second assumption, closely connected with the first, was that moral
and rational advancement would occur. There was a general faith in histor-
ical progress – a confidence that things were improving and would continue
to get better. This optimism was a legacy of Enlightenment thought, but it
also reflected a widespread nineteenth-century belief in secular and scientific
advancement. Some of our thinkers went through pessimistic periods when
it seemed to them that humanity was destined temporarily to regression,
4 Anarchists are often characterised as woolly-minded romantics who rejected science and the modern
world. Albert Lindemann, for example, writes that anarchists ‘were distrustful . . . of modern progress
and of “scientific” or deterministic answers to what they considered the ultimately unpredictable
situations of life’ (Lindemann 1983,p.158). This descriptive statement fits only a minority of anarchist
writers, most notably a group of late nineteenth-century cultural anarchists. This is not to deny that
anarchist thinkers differed concerning the importance of science. Marie Fleming correctly points
out, for example, that spiritual descendants of Bakunin like Reclus and Kropotkin added a ‘scientific’
dimension that was largely absent from the writings of Bakunin himself (Fleming 1988,p.22).
438