16.3 Internal consistency of quantum reasoning 223
projectors: It contains the history identity
˘
I; if it contains a projector Y, then it
also contains its negation I − Y; and if it contains Y and Y
, then it also contains
YY
= Y
Y. These assertions follow at once from the fact that they are true of each
of the F
j
. Furthermore, the fact that each F
j
is a consistent family means that F
is consistent; one can use the criterion in (10.21).
Since each F
j
contains the projectors needed to represent the initial data, along
with those needed to express the conclusions one is interested in, the same is true of
F. Consequently, the task of assigning probabilities using the initial data together
with the dynamical weights of the histories, and then using probabilistic arguments
to reach certain conclusions, can be carried out in F. But since it can be done in
F, it can also be done in an identical fashion in any of the F
j
, as the latter contains
all the projectors of F . Furthermore, any history in F will be assigned the same
weight in F andinanyF
j
, since the weight W(Y) is defined directly in terms of the
history projector Y using a formula, (10.11), that makes no reference to the family
which contains the projector. Consequently, the conclusions one draws from initial
data about physical properties or histories will be identical in all frameworks which
contain the appropriate projectors.
This internal consistency is illustrated by the discussion of the third (last) ques-
tion in Sec. 16.2: F is the family based on the sample space containing (16.6), and
F
1
and F
2
are two mutually incompatible refinements containing the histories in
(16.7) and (16.8), respectively. One can use either F
1
or F
2
to answer the question
“Where is the particle at t = 2?”, and the answer is the same.
As well as providing a proof of consistency, the preceding remarks suggest a
certain strategy for carrying out quantum reasoning of the type we are concerned
with: Use the smallest, or coarsest framework which contains both the initial data
and the additional properties of interest in order to analyze the problem. Any other
framework which can be used for the same purpose will be a refinement of the
coarsest one, and will give the same answers, so there is no point in going to extra
effort. If one has some specific initial data in mind, but wants to consider a variety
of possible conclusions, some of which are incompatible with others, then start off
with the coarsest framework E which contains all the initial data, and refine it in
the different ways needed to draw different conclusions.
This was the strategy employed in Sec. 16.2, except that the coarsest sample
space that contains the initial data X
∗
consists of the two projectors X
∗
and
˘
I −X
∗
,
whereas we used a sample space (16.1) containing three histories rather than just
two. One reason for using X
◦
and X
z
in this case is that each has a straightforward
physical interpretation, unlike their sum
˘
I − X
∗
. The argument for consistency
given above shows that there is no harm in using a more refined sample space
as a starting point for further refinements, as long as it allows one to answer the