In entirely similar manner, Gilbert and Mulkay have analysed
numerous conversations, discourses and texts by scientists to identify
two rhetorical repertoires. The first, what they call the ‘contingent’
repertoire, dominates informal discussions, laboratory work, notes
and intermediate accounts; the second, the empiricist repertoire, is
used in every form of official presentation, from a conference paper
to the official speech made by the scientists when receiving an award
(Gilbert and Mulkay, 1984).
Although the laboratory studies approach does not deny that scien-
tific activity tends to standardize methods and procedures, an aspect
constantly stressed is the strongly local and idiosyncratic character
of the procedures by which a scientific fact is created. Every exper-
imental setting, every laboratory, even the performance of the same
experiment by different researchers, is characterized by a specific
pattern of skills, manual techniques and materials.
2
Apparently
insignificant events like the escape of a laboratory guinea pig may
sometimes significantly alter the entire course of a research project.
For his celebrated public experiment on the anthrax vaccine, Pasteur
had to use sheep instead of the cows that he had planned because
the latter were much dearer to the hearts of the farmers who had
volunteered to make their animals available for his experiment
(Cadeddu, 1987; Bucchi, 1997; see also Section 3, pp. 70ff.).
This aspect marks a result but also a methodological shortcoming
of laboratory studies in regard to the generalizability of observations
made in specific settings.
However, the criticism most frequently brought against laboratory
studies obviously centres on the concept of ‘construction of scientific
fact’. The extent to which this criticism is justified depends among
other things on which version of the argument is selected, because
the degree of ‘constructivism’ varies from author to author – and,
indeed, even among studies made by the same author (Hacking, 1999).
It ranges from an extreme version according to which ‘facts are
consequences rather than causes of scientific descriptions’ to more
moderate versions which claim that ‘what does indeed come into exist-
ence when science “discovers” a microbe or a subatomic particle, it
is a specific entity distinguished from other entities . . . and furnished
with a name, a set of descriptors, and a set of techniques in terms of
which it can be produced and handled’ (Knorr-Cetina, 1995: 161).
Constructionism did not argue the absence of material reality
from scientific activities; it just asked that ‘reality’ or ‘nature’ be
considered as entities continually rentranscibed from within
111
011
111
0111
0111
0111
1111
Inside the laboratory 65