
Mathematics and the Laws of Thermodynamics 143
phenomena have been modeled in conceptually similar ways.
Electromagnetic phenomena, nuclear phenomena, and quantum
mechanical phenomena all demanded their own laws of nature,
and these proved to be very distinct from those governing classical
mechanics and thermodynamics. In each case, the laws formed a
basis for a new science, enabling engineers and scientists to cre-
ate new knowledge by reasoning deductively—their conclusions
always subject to additional experimental verification. No single
volume is sufficient to describe all of these deductive systems, but
the classical laws remain an excellent representative of all such
laws of nature. The preceding chapters reveal several important
characteristics that all laws of nature share.
First, every law of nature must be generalizable, which is anoth-
er way of saying that it must apply in circumstances other than the
ones in which it was first observed to apply. The more generaliz-
able the law, the more useful it is. Under certain circumstances,
for example, Leonardo’s conservation of volume law can be used
to investigate the flow of fluids such as water or air, but because
the conservation of mass law applies to a broader array of situa-
tions—in particular, it can be used anywhere that the conservation
of volume law is used—it is the better choice.
Second, laws of nature should be “fundamental” in the same
way that mathematical axioms are fundamental. Laws of nature
are not logical consequences of other phenomena. They are the
starting point from which reasoning begins. Within classical phys-
ics, for example, one cannot explain the assertion that energy is
conserved. Instead, the assertion that energy is conserved is used
to explain other phenomena. Similar statements are true for the
laws of conservation of mass and momentum. As has been pointed
out several times, experiments exist that demonstrate that mass,
for example, is not always conserved but within the class of phenom-
ena considered in classical physics, mass is a conserved quantity, and
the assumption that it is not conserved in “classical processes” will
yield results that are at variance with experiment.
Third, as mentioned at the beginning of this book, laws of nature
must be consistent in the sense that one cannot prove something
both true and false as a consequence of a set of natural laws.