
Dimension Theory 123
which are often highly technical, we must rely on examples of
continua—especially Richard Dedekind’s construction of the real
line, which is described in chapter 3—to develop some insight into
what continua are. Even so, we would also do well to remember
Dedekind’s cautious description of the relationship of his math-
ematical work to physical space. He wrote that the assertion that
space is continuous is an axiom. “If space has at all a real existence
it is not necessary for it to be continuous; many of its properties
just barely distinguishable. In other words, our observations allow us
to establish that A is not the same as B, but if A were much closer to
B, they would be too close to tell apart. Consequently, if we choose a
point C that is midway between A and B, then C will be indistinguish-
able from both A and B. Our observations would, therefore, indicate
that A = C, C = B, and A ≠ B. (The symbol ≠ means “not equal to.”) To
Poincairé, the idea that A could equal C and C equal B and yet A and
B be unequal was intolerable. (Recall Euclid’s first axiom: “Things which
are equal to the same thing are also equal to one another.”) Poincairé’s
solution was to require that any mathematical model of physical space
have the property that one can always distinguish between points, no
matter how closely they are positioned, and, in addition, he required that
between any pair of points there was always a third point. As a subset
of the real line, however, the set of rational numbers has the properties
that Poincairé wanted. (Between any two rational numbers, for example,
there is always a third.) Yet, even Pythagoras, knew that the set of ratio-
nal numbers is not sufficient to describe the simplest geometric figures.
(The length of the diagonal of the square with sides one unit long, for
example, is √2, an irrational number.)
Mathematicians responded to these observations by creating the
concept of a continuum, a purely mathematical concept. There is no
reason to suppose that there exists a physical analogue to a math-
ematical continuum, nor can any experiment or observation resolve the
question of whether space, or time, or space-time forms a continuum
in the sense understood by mathematicians. Still, having agreed upon
a definition of the concept of continuum, a definition that satisfied the
needs of mathematicians, topologists spent decades investigating the
logical implications of that definition. The result is a remarkable body of
theorems that demonstrate just how large a gap separates the discover-
ies of modern mathematics from common sense notions of continuity.
That gap continues to grow.