
357 12.3 Cosmological dynamics: understanding the expanding universe
t
This has the solution
R
2
=
-
32
3
πB
.
1/2
(t −T), (12.57)
where T is a constant of integration. So, indeed, R = 0 was achieved at a finite time in the
past, and we conventionally adjust our zero of time so that R = 0att = 0, which means
we redefine t so that T = 0.
Note that we have found that a radiation-dominated cosmology with no cosmological
constant has an expansion rate where R(t) ∝ t
1/2
. If we had done this computation for a
matter-dominated cosmology with ρ
= 0, we would have found R(t) ∝ t
2/3
(see Exer. 19,
§ 12.6).
What happens if there is a cosmological constant? If the dark energy is positive, there is
no qualitative change in the conclusion, since the term involving ρ
simply increases the
value of
˙
R at any value of R, and this brings the time where R = 0 closer to the present
epoch. If the matter density has always been positive, and if the cosmological constant is
non-negative, then Einstein’s equations make the Big Bang inevitable: the universe began
with R = 0 at a finite time in the past. This is called the cosmological singularity:the
curvature tensor is singular, tidal forces become infinitely large, and Einstein’s equations
do not allow us to continue the solution to earlier times. Within the Einstein framework we
cannot ask questions about what came before the Big Bang: time simply began there.
How certain, then, is our conclusion that the universe began with a Big Bang? First, we
must ask if isotropy and homogeneity were crucial; the answer is no. The ‘singularity theo-
rems’ of Penrose and Hawking (see Hawking and Ellis 1973) have shown that our universe
certainly had a singularity in its past, regardless of how asymmetric it may have been. But
the theorems predict only the existence of the singularity: the nature of the singularity is
unknown, except that it has the property that at least one particle in the present universe
must have originated in it. Nevertheless, the evidence is strong indeed that we all origi-
nated in it. Another consideration however is that we don’t know the laws of physics at
the incredibly high densities (ρ →∞) which existed in the early universe. The singularity
theorems of necessity assume (1) something about the nature of T
μν
, and (2) that Einstein’s
equations (without cosmological constant) are valid at all R.
The assumption about the positivity of the energy density of matter can be challenged
if we allow quantum effects. As we saw in our discussion of the Hawking radiation in the
previous chapter, fluctuations can create negative energy for short times. In principle, there-
fore, our conclusions are not reliable if we are within one Planck time t
Pl
= GM
Pl
/c
2
∼
10
−43
s of the Big Bang! (Recall the definition of the Planck mass in Eq. (11.111).) This
is the domain of quantum gravity, and it may well turn out that, when we have a quantum
theory of the gravitational interaction, we will find that the universe has a history before
what we call the Big Bang.
Philosophically satisfying as this might be, it has little practical relevance to the universe
we see today. We might not be able to start our universe model evolving from t = 0, but
we can certainly start it from, say, t = 100t
Pl
within the Einstein framework. The primary
uncertainties about understanding the physical cosmology that we see around us are, as
we will discuss below, to be found in the physics of the early universe, not in the time
immediately around the Big Bang.