
2Ó2
Natural philosophy
thinkers, and Bruno in particular, who had opened up the new vistas in
cosmology.
21
Galileo,
however, often suppressed their names and in any
case had been educated in a different tradition. Moreover, he displayed a
lively
awareness of purpose and method which cannot be reconciled with
any
legacy
to him from, for instance, Campanella.
22
But Galileo's
distinction between the written book of God and the book of
nature
resembles a similar distinction in Bruno's thought, and the similarity is not
diminished by the different emphasis
that
both gave to mathematics. For
Galileo
as
well,
to establish the mathematical laws of the cosmos using a
yardstick
that
was adequate to what had been God's procedure and also such
that
our awareness was on the same qualitative,
if
not quantitative, plane as
divine awareness, meant to possess a key capable of unlocking God's
modus
operandi
and the secret intentions of his legislative
will
in
nature.
In other
words,
his discoveries also coincided with the emergence of a revelation.
Galileo's
relationship with the philosophy
of
nature
shows equally clearly
its limits within the scientific revolution. By rejecting, as Aristotle had
done, the possibility of a mathematical account of physical phenomena
which
was not merely a
matter
of practical approximations but which
might reveal their deepest structures
—
that
is, by favouring the notion of a
ceaseless coming-into-being which could not be understood in terms of an
intelligible
structure
—
the philosophy of
nature
was in opposition to both
Galileo
and Descartes. It was not by chance
that
Descartes noted the
efficacy
of
the work of the
novatores
more in the context of the criticism of
Aristotelian philosophy
than
in the construction of a new philosophy.
23
The methodological characteristics
of
the philosophy
of
nature
appeared to
be inadequate in the face
of
new scientific developments, especially those in
physics.
Certainly, the programme outlined in the
Discours
de la
méthode
developed at its highest
level
as a realisation of a scientific morality and as a
reform
of
the human world, moving from the individual plane to
that
of
the
dominion of the human race over
nature
and the transformation of man's
intentions towards it. But the Cartesian dream of a
mathesis
universalis
had
already allied itself with the
attempt
to construct a new metaphysical
foundation for the new learning.
24
Other factors, however, worked to prolong the influence of the
philosophy of
nature.
The initially limited achievements of mathematical
21. See
Kepler
1610.
22.
Galilei
1890-1909,
iv, p. 738: 'Io
stimo
più il
trovar
un
vero,
benché
di
cosa
leggiera,
che '1
disputar
lungamente
delle
massime
questioni
senza
verità
nissuna.'
23. See, e.g.,
Descartes
1897-1910,
1, pp.
156-70
(letter
to
Isaac
Beeckman,
17
October
1630).
24. See
Gilson
1951.
Cambridge Histories Online © Cambridge University Press, 2008