According to Eriugena, God is not good but more than good, not wise
but more than wise, not eternal but more than eternal. This language, of
course, does not really add anything, except a tone of awe, to the denial
that any of these predicates are literally true of God. Eriugena even goes
as far as to say that God is not God but more than God. So too with
the individual persons of the Trinity: the Father is not a Father except
metaphorically.
Among the Aristotelian categories that, according to Eriugena, are to be
denied of God are those of action and passion. God neither acts nor is acted
upon, except metaphorically: strictly he neither moves nor is moved,
neither loves nor is loved. The Bible tells us that God loves and is loved,
but that has to be interpreted in the light of reason. Reason is superior to
authority; authority is derived from reason and not vice versa; reason does
not require any conW rmation from authority. Reason tells us that the Bible
is not using nouns and verbs in their proper sense, but using allegories and
metaphors to go to meet our childish intelligence. ‘Nothing can be said
properly about God, since he surpasses every intellect, who is better known
by not knowing, of whom ignorance is the true knowledge, who is more
truly and faithfully denied in all things than aYrmed’ (Periphyseon, 1).
Our knowledge of God, such as it is, is derived both from the metaphor-
ical statements of theology and from ‘theophanies’, or manifestations of
God to particular persons, such as the visions of the prophets. God’s
essence is unknown to men and angels: indeed, it is unknown to God
himself. Just as I, a human being, know that I am, but not what I am, so God
does not know what he is. If he did, he would be able to deW ne himself; but
the inWnite cannot be deWned. It is no insult to God to say that he does not
know what he is; for he is not a what (Periphyseon, 2).
In describing the relation between God and his creatures Eriugena uses
language which is easily interpreted as a form of pantheism, and it was this
that led to his condemnation by a Pope three and a half centuries later.
God, he says, may be said to be created in creatures, to be made in the
things he makes, and to begin to be in the things that begin to be
(Periphyseon, 1. 12). Just as our intellect creates its own life by engaging in
actual thinking, so too God, in giving life to creatures, is making a life for
himself. To those who regarded such statements as Xatly incompatible with
Christian orthodoxy, Eriugena could no doubt have replied that, like all
other positive statement s about God, they were only metaphors.
GOD
287