the philosophy of plato
45
son and the heir to his argument, defends the hypothesis that justice is doing
good to one’s friends and harm to one’s enemies. The refutation of this sugges-
tion takes longer; but finally Polemarchus agrees that it is not just to harm any
man at all. The crucial premiss needed for this elenchus is that justice is human
excellence or virtue. It is preposterous, Socrates urges, to think that a just man
could exercise his excellence by making others less excellent.
Polemarchus is knocked out of the debate because he accepts without a mur-
mur the premiss that justice is human excellence; but waiting in the wings is the
sophist Thrasymachus, agog to challenge that hypothesis. Justice is not a virtue or
excellence, he says, but weakness and foolishness, because it is not in anyone’s
interest to possess it. On the contrary, justice is simply what is to the advantage of
those who have power in the state; law and morality are only systems designed for
the protection of their interests. It takes Socrates twenty pages and some complic-
ated forking procedures to checkmate Thrasymachus; but eventually, at the end
of Book One, it is agreed that the just man will have a better life than the unjust
man, so that justice is in its possessor’s interests. Thrasymachus is driven to agree
by a number of concessions he makes to Socrates. For instance, he agrees that the
gods are just, that human virtue or excellence makes one happy. These and other
premisses need arguing for; all of them can be questioned and most of them are
questioned elsewhere in the Republic, from Book Two onwards.
Two people who have so far listened silently to the debate are Plato’s brothers
Glaucon and Adeimantus. Glaucon intervenes to suggest that while justice may not
be a positive evil, as Thrasymachus had suggested, it is not something worthwhile
for its own sake, but something chosen as a way of avoiding evil. To avoid being
oppressed by others, weak human beings make compacts with each other neither
to suffer nor to commit injustice. People would much prefer to act unjustly,
if they could do so with impunity – the kind of impunity a man would have, for
instance, if he could make himself invisible so that his misdeeds passed undetected.
Adeimantus supports his brother, saying that among humans the rewards of justice
are the rewards of seeming to be just rather than the rewards of actually being
just, and with regard to the gods the penalties of injustice can be bought off by
prayer and sacrifice. If Socrates is really to defeat Thrasymachus, he must show
that quite apart from reputation, and quite apart from sanctions, justice is in itself
as much preferable to injustice as sight is to blindness and health is to sickness.
In response, Socrates shifts from the consideration of justice in the individual
to the consideration of justice in the city-state. There, he says, the nature of
justice will be written in larger letters and easier to read. The purpose of living in
cities is to enable people with different skills to supply each others’ needs. Ideally,
if people were content with the satisfaction of their basic needs, a very simple
community would suffice. But citizens demand more than mere subsistence, and
this necessitates a more complicated structure, providing, among other things, for
a well-trained professional army.
AIBC03 22/03/2006, 10:38 AM45