Romanticism and political thought in the early nineteenth century
pp. 23–5). The socially beneficial balance of these proprietorial interests
was facilitated by the unifying impulses produced by the Crown, and was
augmented by the interaction between Parliament and the invigorating but
potentially destabilising influence of extra-parliamentary forces (Coleridge
1976,pp.41–2;Morrow1990,pp.133–40). ‘Permanence’ and ‘progres-
sion’ were not ‘interests’ in the conventional sense and were not part of a
mechanical balance. Rather, they were aspects, or moments, of an organic
social and political order. They were important because they embodied
complementary states of mind that reflected ‘progressive’ and ‘perma-
nent’ forces within society, not because of their physical mass. Coleridge
used the language of balance as an electro-magnetic, not as a mechanical
metaphor.
5
The moral significance of landed property was emphasised in Coleridge’s
second ‘Lay Sermon’ of 1817, a work produced in reaction to the hardship
and dislocation that accompanied the peace of 1815. He claimed that the
ends of landed property were identical with those of the state and attributed
many of the ills of post-war Britain to an ‘overbalance of the ‘commercial
spirit’ (Coleridge 1972,p.169). These remarks reflected Coleridge’s concern
that the landed classes’ endorsement of commercial values was undermining
an essential counterpoise within the state. The cupidity and extravagance
of the gentry was given an air of intellectual plausibility by the faddish
‘science’ of political economy, but Coleridge insisted that this discipline
did not adequately specify the duties and responsibilities of statesmen or
the landed gentry (Coleridge 1972,pp.169–70, 210–16; Kennedy 1958;
Morrow 1990,pp.115–21).
At the heart of this critique of political economy and of the gentry’s
seduction by it, was a romantic view of the implications of enlightened
rationalism. Like Southey and Wordsworth, Coleridge believed that the
self-interested practical materialism of the gentry was a consequence of the
5 See, for example, the references to ‘poles’ (Coleridge 1976,p.24 note ∗ and p. 35). John Colmer points
to a parallel between Coleridge’s conception of polarity and those of his German contemporaries;
‘the dynamic unity of nature, of life, and of thought was conceived as arising from a synthesis of
opposing forces’ (Coleridge 1976,p.35 n3). A strong theory of polarity plays an important role in
M
¨
uller’s political thought (see p. 54) but I can find no evidence that Coleridge was aware of his
work. Coleridge’s interest in aspects of German thought has been widely studied (see, for example,
Harding 1986; MacKinnon 1974;Orsini1969), but there is little to suggest a direct link between his
political ideas and those of German romantic writers. Schlegel’s Geschichte der alten und neuen Litteratur
(1815) played an important role in Coleridge’s literary lectures in 1818–19, but apart from this there
are only brief references to Schleiermacher’s writings on prayer in his correspondence and notebooks
and a short, not politically interesting comment on Novalis in his marginalia (Coleridge 1987, ii,
pp. 32, 46, 53–61, 1956–71, vi,pp.543, 545–6, 555, 1980–, ii,p.958).
49