Counter-revolutionary thought
and took him far closer to liberals such as Constant. In his Essai sur les
Institutions Sociales dans leurs Rapports avec les Id
´
ees Nouvelles of 1818, Ballanche
grafted a new component of progress on to his theory of the divine nature
of social institutions. Maistre complained that Ballanche’s ‘excellent heart’
had become corr upted by a ‘revolutionary spirit’. In fact, Ballanche was
still opposed to the notion of popular sovereignty, but he had now added
into his political theory a notion of popular consent. Providence, he now
argued, worked gradually to increase equality in the civil realm, in line
with Christian equality. The only way for French monarchs to retain their
legitimacywastomoveinthedirectionofF
´
enelon’s ideal king and away
from absolutism. Those kings were most legitimate who showed the greatest
F
´
enelonian love for their people. Ballanche famously remarked that Maistre
was the ‘prophet of the past’ because he sought to return France to a social
order whose time had passed, whereas F
´
enelon was the ‘prophet of the
future’ (quoted in McAlla 1998,p.325).
In 1827, Ballanche took the idea of social progress still further, with his
new concept of ‘social palingenesis’, which was a self-conscious attempt
to link the liberty of the liberals with the unity of the right-wing Ultras
(Ballanche 1833, iv; see also McAlla 1998, Part Three, ‘Social Palingenesis’).
In biology, ‘palingenesis’ was the theory, associated with Charles Bonnet,
that living beings contain within themselves a tiny pre-for med structure,
which only has to be fertilised to start growing. This, coupled with some
illuminist currents of esoteric history, gave Ballanche the idea that each
historical era contains within itself the germ of the next age. Thus Ballanche
could simultaneously hold to the notion of divine providence – because
the initial germs were all made by God – and that of human progress –
because certain humans (whom Ballanche called ‘initiators’) had the power
to bring these germs to fruition. Moreover, the direction of history was
democratic: each change in era brought nearer the gradual emancipation of
the whole human race. The hero of Ballanche’s history is not the king but
the plebeian. Ballanche restores the element of individual will to ‘volont
´
e
g
´
en
´
erale’. When new European revolutions took place in the 1820s–in
Spain, Naples, Piedmont and Greece – Ballanche welcomed them as a sign
of providentially governed social evolution. In contrast to Maistre, Ballanche
now saw revolutions as part of Christian history, rather than a departure from
it; Maistre and Bonald had failed, he wrote, ‘to understand the new facts’
of the ‘new society’ (Ballanche 1833, ii,p.348).
By the late 1820s, with the Restoration well underway, there was a new
tradition of Catholic social thought in France emerging, sometimes labelled
37