Historians and lawyers
and an antiquary whose doctrine was not so much false as ‘unmeaning’.
According to Blackstone, ‘That ancient collection of unwritten maxims
and customs, which is the common law, however confounded and from
whatever foundation derived, had subsisted immemorially in this kingdom’
(Blackstone 1862,p.16). To Bentham this was nonsense; and his first charge
was ‘to the science [of law] of the poison introduced into it by him’ (Black-
stone 1862,p.16, cf . Bentham 2008). What Bentham wanted to do was
to transform unwritten custom into written law, common law into statute
law, and vague and confused legal memory into a rational system based not
on the muddled ideals of justice but on the calculable goals fixed by utility
and a general theory of human nature.
From these attitudes arose Bentham’s projects for judicial organisation,
beginning with a new plan drawn up for the benefit of the French National
Assembly in December 1789 and ending with a proposal addressed in 1822
to ‘All Nations professing Liberal Opinions’ (Bentham 1789, 1822). Join-
ing together ‘principles of morals and legislation’, Bentham assumed that
individual psychology (especially the ‘associationist’ psychology of David
Hartley) was a sufficient basis not only for social theory but also for public
policy. In general Bentham’s system was based on a general contempt for
history, a simplistic theory of human behaviour, and a legislative strategy
governed by a ‘calculus’ of pleasures and pains and the attendant principle
of utility; and his logical-intuitive approaches offered a ‘radical’ alternative
to both the historical and the natural-law schools of jurisprudence. To his
followers, Bentham was a supreme theorist of the science of legislation; to
others, such as William Hazlitt, he was a ‘mere child’ and an unfortunate
sign of the times (Hazlitt 1828,p.172).
Bentham’s attitudes were carried more directly into the law by his dis-
ciple John Austin, whose Lectures on Jurisprudence were subtitled, borrowing
a phrase from Gustav Hugo, ‘the philosophy of positive law’. Austin was
as remote as possible, however, from the ideas of the historical school and
its reverence for popular custom as the ultimate source of law. Nonsense,
declared Austin; custom became law not by the consent of the governed
but by command of the state. Nor was ‘interpretation’ a qualification of this
argument, for interpretation was nothing else than ‘establishing new laws,
under guise of expounding the old’ (Austin 1873, i,p.27; Morison 1982).
Nor was this at all objectionable. ‘I cannot understand how any person
who has considered the subject can suppose that society could possibly have
gone on if judges had not legislated, or that there is any danger whatever
in allowing them that power which they have in fact exercised, to make up
163