Hegel and Hegelianism
Schelling to Berlin ‘to combat the dragonseed of Hegelianism’. Then, in
1842, the government began to impose censorship, forcing the Hegelians to
publish their main journal, the Hallische Jahrb
¨
ucher, outside Prussia. For any
Hegelian in the 1840s, then, this course of events could only be profoundly
discouraging. Rather than marching forward, as Hegel assumed, history
seemed to be moving backwards.
Once the forces of reaction began to assert themselves, it was inevitable
that Hegel’s philosophy would collapse. The very essence of Hegel’s teaching
made him vulnerable to historical refutation. The great strength of Hegel’s
system lay in its bold syntheses – of theory and practice, of rationalism and
historicism, or radicalism and conservatism – for these seemed to transcend
the partisan spirit, granting every standpoint a necessary, if limited, place
in the whole. But the great strength of Hegel’s philosophy was also its
great weakness, its tragic flaw. For, as we have seen, all these syntheses
rested upon a single optimistic premise: that reason is inherent in history,
that the laws and trends of history will inevitably realise the ideals of the
Revolution. It was just this optimism, though, that seemed to be refuted by
the disillusioning events of the early 1840s. Hegel had bet his whole system
on history; and he had lost.
It is not surprising to find, then, that the neo-Hegelian debates of the
1840s take on a new dimension. The question is no longer how to praise
and interpret Hegel but how to transform and bury him. The publication
of Feuerbach’s Das Wesen des Christenthums in 1841 convinced many of the
need to go beyond Hegel. In 1842, Arnold Ruge, a leading left Hegelian,
published his first criticism of Hegel.
44
And in 1843 Marx and Engels would
begin their ‘settling of accounts’ with their Hegelian heritage in Die deutsche
Ideologie. Internal feuding lost its former energy and meaning. Many of the
right-wing Hegelians became disillusioned with the course of events and
joined their brothers on the left to form a common front against their
reactionary enemies (Toews 1980,pp.223–4). The common framework for
the debates of the 1830s also quickly disappeared. Rather than reaffirming
the ideal of the unity of theory and practice, many Hegelians asserted the
rights of theory over practice. It seemed to Bruno Bauer, for example, that
the growing gap between ideal and reality in Friedrich Wilhelm’s Prussia
could be overcome only by ‘the terror ism of pure theory’.
44 McLellan 1969,p.24. The new critical developments of the 1840s are well-summarised by Stepelvich
1983,pp.12–15.
145