On the principle of nationality
Second, race arguments acquired a new force following the publication
of Darwin’s Origins of Species in 1859.
44
Popularisation of the notion of
necessary struggle, leading to ‘survival of the fittest’ could be applied in
racial terms.
45
Whether in Darwinian or non-Darwinian form (denying
common origins to races), the idea of race became explicitly biological.
This radicalised and essentialised difference and justified hierarchy or
separation or ultimately murder.
46
Third, these arguments were extended into Europe, underpinning claims
about Germanic, Latin and Slav peoples, or the distinct racial qualities of
Jews.
47
Rapid industrial and urban growth and cross-border immigration
brought together ethnically distinct peoples, often in conflict over jobs and
housing. Germany became a country of net immigration from the 1890s,
just as race ideas were applied to poor Polish, Russian and Jewish immi-
grants. Conversely, pogroms against Jews in western Russia contributed
to this migration and also were justified with race arguments. The rapid
development of mass politics was associated with a populist nationalism
reacting against elite nationalism and the class and confessional creeds of
labour and Catholic parties. Radical nationalism, including anti-Semitism,
figured prominently in such populist politics.
48
Nevertheless, perceiving national difference within Europe as a mat-
ter of biological race was still marginal by 1914. In Western Europe the
44 Ironically Darwin later lost influence amongst biologists because he was unable to explain the
selective transmission of favoured differences, indeed his assumption that traits from parents were
mixed in their offspring undermined his own argument of selection. Only after 1918,withthe
rediscovery of Mendel’s findings on genetic selection, did the rise of neo-Darwinism beg in. See
Kohn 2004.
45 The phrase ‘survival of the fittest’ was in fact coined by Herbert Spencer in relation to competition
between human beings, both individuals and societies, but acquired a pseudo-scientific meaning
through its association with Darwin’s notion of evolution. There is a huge literature on this subject.
For a good introduction to the ‘internal’ intellectual history of the subject, see Banton 1998.
46 Even if one assumed – as the influence of Darwin largely led most thinkers to do – common origins
and progressive evolution, the time span involved meant this had no practical significance where
people perceived major racial differences. Much depended on further beliefs about how traits were
inherited and what would be the consequences of racial interbreeding. Beliefs of the time tended
towards purity, hierarchy and discrimination. Whereas Mill and Michelet had envisaged advantageous
racial blends, this was excluded from the later discourse of biological race.
47 One telling example is how the interest in classifying peoples through skull measurement, taken up
in overseas empire, was extended in Germany with a similar exercise – this time involving hair, skin
and eye colour – carried out in many schools and treating Jews as distinctive in these respects. As
the survey involved some six million pupils, one can imagine that it also had some impact on the
attitudes of many young Germans. See Zimmermann 2004.
48 Again, the literature is vast. Generally see MacMaster 2001. For a good comparative survey for Britain
and Germany, see Kennedy and Nicholls 1981. For a specific example of populist nationalism see
Coetzee 1990.
105