angry. You know, this Abu Ghraib, it would change your whole mind frame.
You know you can go from being a docile, jolly guy.... And you go to Abu
Ghraib for a while, you become a robot.”
7
For Zimbardo, President George W. Bush, Vice President Dick Cheney and
Secretary of Defense Donald Rumsfeld created a system of authority that
implicitly or explicitly encouraged acts of torture, and in early 2002 the Bush
administration decided that the Geneva Conventions (signed by the United
States in 1949) did not apply in this situation. Feeding down the chain of
command, military intelligence and private contractors encouraged the
amateur guards at Abu Ghraib to “soften up” the prisoners for interrogation. It
was the barrel they made, then, that turned basically good people bad. On the
other hand, the Bush administration blamed the dispositions of the individuals
themselves. “A new Iraq will also need a humane, well-supervised prison
system. Under the dictator, prisons like Abu Ghraib were symbols of death and
torture,” Bush argued. “That same prison became a symbol of disgraceful
conduct by a few American troops who dishonored our country and disregarded
our values.”
We have repeatedly noted that situationism presents a challenge to the
Western legal system and its basic notion that individuals are responsible for
their own choices and actions. In The Lucifer Effect, Zimbardo relates the prob-
lems this created when he tried to help the defense of Sergeant Ivan “Chip”
Frederick, one of the soldiers who was photographed grinning beside a pyra-
mid of naked Iraqi prisoners. Although Zimbardo had mixed feelings about
becoming involved in defending Frederick, he agreed to testify in his trial via
videoconference. In Frederick’s defense, Zimbardo argued that Frederick was
a psychologically normal (if insecure and indecisive) individual who found
himself in a highly abnormal situation. While Zimbardo did not attempt to
excuse Frederick, he did seek to better understand his actions and perhaps to get
situational factors considered in the defendant’s sentencing. Someone like
Frederick, he argued, could actually have been a hero if he’d been in a “better
barrel,” but he was in many ways in the wrong place at the wrong time.
Predictably, this argument was rejected by the judge, who adopted a more
traditional dispositionist view: Frederick, he said, had chosen his actions of his
own free will, and no one had coerced him to act in unethical ways.
Again, it is for the reader to decide himself or herself who is right. To what
extent did the barrel rot the apples, or were the apples rotten from the start?
This issue, as we’ve seen repeatedly, lies at the very heart of the situationist–
dispositionist debate. Whatever you conclude, however, it is worth noting that
there are those for whom the situation does not take over, individuals whose
basic moral sense is more difficult to bypass. In the Stanford case, Christina
Maslach—despite powerful situational pressures to conform (Zimbardo was
66 The Situation