Tuesday is by finding out if it’s the second day of the week. And so on.
Well, according to Putnam, if a concept has, in this sense, only one
criterion, then it is conceptually necessary (viz. constitutive of the content
of the concept) that if the criterion is satisfied then the concept applies. So
there is, after all, an epistemic clause in the theory of concept constitutivity.
Old timers will recognize this treatment of BACHELOR and the like as
close kin to the then-popular theory that DOG, CAUSE, PAIN, FORCE,
WATER, INFLUENZA, and the like are “cluster” concepts. In effect, a
cluster concept is one for whose application there are lots of criteria.
So, then, according to Putnam, analyticity just is one-criterionhood.
The problems with this account by now seem pretty obvious; we’ll return
to them in a moment. First, however, a word or two in its praise.
To begin with, it deconfounds analyticity from centrality, thereby
freeing embarrassed Quineans from having to assimilate bachelors are
unmarried to F = MA. It also deconfounds analyticity from mere necessity
in a way that intuition applauds. As I remarked above, it’s necessary that
bachelors are unmarried, and it’s again necessary that two is prime, but
only the first seems to be a good candidate for a conceptual necessity since
one isn’t much tempted by the thought that not having the concept
PRIME entails not having the concept TWO. Putnam’s story works very
well here. It is precisely because two is enmeshed in a rich—indeed an
infinite—network of necessities that one hesitates to choose among them
the ones that constitute the content of the concept. Given the plethora of
necessary inferences that TWO can mediate, who’s to say which ones your
having the concept requires that you acknowledge? Similarly with the
logical particles. And similarly, too, for FORCE and DOG (though the
necessities that embed these concepts are characteristically metaphysical
and/or nomic rather than mathematical or logical). In short, the less work
a concept does, the stronger the analyticity intuitions that it is able to
support; just as Putnam’s account of conceptual connectedness predicts.
And since being well connected to the web, like being near the web’s
centre, is a matter of degree, Putnam’s story explains straight off why
intuitions of analyticity are graded. Nobody seriously doubts that
bachelors being unmarried is a better candidate for analyticity than dogs
being animals, which is in turn a better candidate than F’s being MA,
which is in turn at least as bad a candidate as two’s being prime. The
gradedness of analyticity intuitions suggests some sort of epistemic
construal if the alternative explanation is that they arise from such
structural relations among concepts as containment. Containment, unlike
criteriality, doesn’t plausibly come in more or less.
So there are nice things to be said for Putnam’s account of analyticity,
and I suppose that Quine’s sympathizers would have jumped at it except
The Philosopher’s Tale
81
Chaps. 3 & 4 11/3/97 1:11 PM Page 81