3
serialism), we are much more likely to construe that music as mathematically induced,
often to the point where we lose interest in it as artistic expression and only derive
stimulation from the work in an intellectual fashion.
The use of explicit algorithms and mathematical models in the construction of
music is, therefore, a risky endeavor at best. With the advent of the digital computer,
many composers have readily committed to the incorporation of abstract mathematical
models into their music. Lejaren Hiller’s Illiac Suite (1957), considered, somewhat
arbitrarily, as the “first algorithmic piece of music” (Chadabe, 1996), in many ways sets
the tone for what has become a slippery slope towards using abstract, non-musical, and
somewhat arbitrary sets of information and equations to generate music. Unfortunately,
the fact that music can be mathematically derived does not necessarily imply that
mathematics makes for good music, using any but the most pedantic evaluation systems.
So what sorts of algorithms make for good music? Theoretical research in music
cognition, psychoacoustics, and contemporary music theory strongly suggests that
musical events are interpreted by the human listener as hierarchical structures, which are
deconstructed on various levels from the musical surface of event streams to the higher-
level perception of musical form, achieved through our musical memory. Various
analytic models are available for discerning these hierarchies, ranging from the
metaphysical (Schenker) to the mathematical (Riemann). One of the most promising
(and logical) theories for deriving musical structure as heard by the listener is based on
linguistics and generative grammar models (Lerdahl and Jackendoff, 1983, Lerdahl,
2001). To turn the tables for a moment, we might posit that algorithmic strategies that
emulate (or, at the very least, take into account) these hierarchical systems (or that