174
POST-KANTIAN IDEALIST SYSTEMS
in
conceptual form, a difficulty
at
once arises. The Absolute
is,
as
we have seen, identity-in-difference. For instance,
it
is the
identity-in-difference of the infinite
and
the finite, of the One and
the
Many.
But
the concepts of infinite and finite, as of the One
and
the Many, seem to be mutually exclusive.
If,
therefore,
philosophy operates with clearly-defined concepts, how can it
possibly construct the life of the Absolute? And if
it
operates with
vague, ill-defined concepts, how can
it
be
an
apt
instrument for
understanding anything? Would
it
not be better to say with
Schelling
that
the Absolute transcends conceptual thought?
In
Hegel's view this difficulty does indeed arise on the level of
understanding
(Verstand). For understanding posits and perpetu-
ates fixed static concepts of such a kind
that
it
cannot itself
overcome the oppositions which
it
posits. To take the same example
which has already been given, for understanding
the
concepts of
the
finite and the infinite are irrevocably opposed.
If
finite, then
not
infi.nite:
if infinite, then not finite. But the conclusion to be
drawn is
that
understanding is an inadequate instrument for the
development of speculative philosophy, not
that
philosophy is
impossible. Obviously, if the term 'understanding'
is taken in a
wide sense, philosophy
is understanding.
But
if the term
is
taken
in
the narrow sense of Verstand, the mind, functioning in this way,
is unable to produce the understanding (in the wide sense) which
is, or ought to be, characteristic
of
philosophy.
Hegelhas, of course, no intention of denying
that
understanding,
in
the sense of the mind operating as Verstand, has its uses in
human life. For practical purposes
it
is often important to maintain
clear-cut concepts and oppositions. The opposition between the
real and the apparent might be a case in point. Moreover, a great
deal of scientific work, such as mathematics, is based
on
Verstand.
But
it
is a different matter when the mind is trying to grasp the
life of the Absolute, the identity-in-difference.
It
cannot then
remain content with the level of understanding, which for Hegel
is
a superficial level.
It
must penetrate deeper into the concepts
which are categories of reality, and
it
will then see how a given
concept tends to pass over into or to call forth its opposite. For
example, if the mind really thinks through,
so
to speak, the concept
of the infinite,
it
sees
it
losing its rigid self-containedness and the
concept of the infinite emerging.
Similarly, if
the
mind really
thinks through the concept of reality as opposed to appearance,
it
will see the absurd or 'contradictory' character of a reality which
HEGEL
(I)
175
in no way
at
all appears or manifests itself. Again, for common
sense and
practiCal life one thing is distinct from all other things;
it is self-identical and negates all other things. And
so
long as
we
are not concerned with thinking what this really means, the idea
has its practical uses. But once
we
really
try
to think it,
we
see the
absurdity
of
the notion of a completely isolated thing, and
we
are
forced to negate the original negation.
Thus in speculative philosophy the mind
must elevate itself
from the level of understanding in the narrow sense to the level of
dialectical thinking which overcomes the rigidity of the concepts
of
the understanding and sees one concept as generating or passing
into its opposite. Only
so
can it hope to grasp the life of the
Absolute in which one moment
or
phase passes necessarily into
another.
But
this
is
obviously not enough.
If
for the understanding
concepts
A and B are irrevocably opposed whereas for the deeper
penetration
of
dialectical thought A passes into
Band
B
into
A,
there must be a higher unity or synthesis which unites
them without annulling their difference. And
it
is
the function
of reason
(Vernunft) to grasp this moment of identity-in-difference.
Hence philosophy demands the elevation
of
understanding through
dialectical thinking to the level of reason or speculative thought
which
is
capable of apprehending identity-In-difference.
1
I t
is
perhaps unnecessary to add
that
from Hegel's point of view
it
is
not a question
of
producing a new species of logic out of the
hat
to enable him to esta.blish an arbitrarily preconceived view of
reality. For he sincerely believes
that
dialectical thought gives a
deeper penetration of the nature of reality
than
understanding in
the narrow sense can possibly
do.
For example, it
is
not for Hegel a
question
of
insisting
that
the concept
·of
the finite must pass over
into or call forth the concept
of
the infinite simply because of a
preconceived belief
that
the infinite exists in and through the
finite. For it
is
his conviction
that
we
cannot really think the
finite without relating it to the infinite.
It
is
not
we
who
do
some-
thing to the concept, juggling about with it, as
it
were: it is the
concept itself which loses its rigidity and breaks up before the
mind's attentive gaze. And this fact reveals to us the nature of the
finite: it has a metaphysical significance.
I
The
terms
'understanding'
and
'reason'
are
not
used in precisely
the
same
ways
by
Kant
and
Hegel. This {act
apart,
however,
the
contrast
between
Kant·,
mistrust
of
the
flights of reason, coupled
with
his admission
of
its
practical
function,
and
Hegel's depreciation of
understanding.
coupled
with
a recognition
of
its
practical
use, well
illustrates
their
respective
attitudes
to
speculative
metaphysics.