POST-KANTIAN IDEALIST SYSTEMS
revelation, in the sense of a freely-imparted knowledge of God.
They can, of course, be consciously elaborated,
but
fundamentally
they are the product
of
an unconscious and necessary process,
successive forms in which
an
apprehension of the divine imposes
itself on the religious consciousness.
In
other words, mythology
corresponds to the dark or lower principle in
God, and
it
has its
roots in the sphere of
the
unconscious. When, however,
we
pass
from mythology to revelation,
we
pass 'into a completely different
sphere'.
1
In
mythology the mind
'had
to do with
a.
necessary
process, here with something which exists only as the result of an
absolutely free
will'.
II
For the concept
of
revelation presupposes an
act whereby God 'freely gives
or
has given himself to mankind'.8
Inasmuch as mythological religion and revealed religion are both
religion,
it
must be possible, Schelling insists, to subsume them
under a common idea. And in fact the whole history of the
religious consciousness
is
a second theogony or birth
of
God, in the
sense
that
the eternal and timeless becoming or birth of God in
himself
4
is represented in time in the history of religion. Mythology,
as rooted
in
the unconscious, represents a moment in the divine
life.
It
logically precedes revelation and
is
a preparation for it. But
it
is not itself revelation. For revelation is essentially God's free
manifestation of himself as infinite, personal and free creator and
lord of being. And, as a free act on God's part,
it
is not simply a
logical consequence of mythology. At the
same time revelation can
be described as the
truth
of mythology. For mythology is, as
it
were, the exoteric element which veils the revealed truth. And in
paganism the philosopher can find mythological representations or
antcipiations of the truth.
In
other words, Schelling wishes to represent the whole history
of the religious consciousness as God's revelation
of
himself, while
at
the same time he wishes to leave room for a specifically Christian
concept of revelation. On the one hand revelation, in what
we
might perhaps caIl a weak sense
of
the term, runs through the
whole history of religion. For
it
is the inner
truth
of mythology.
On
the other hand revelation in a strong sense of the term is found in
Christianity. For
it
is in the Christian religion
that
this inner truth
first comes to the clear light of day.
Christianity thus gives the
truth
of mythology, and it can be described as the culmination of
historical religion.
But
it
does not follow
that
Christianity is an
lW,
VI,
p. 396. I Ibid. • W,
VI,
p. 395.
•
The
reference is
to
the
logically distinguishable 'potencies'
in
God's inner life.
SCHELLING
(3)
I4I
automatic consequence of mythology. Mythology as such is, as
we
have seen, a necessary process.
But
in and through Christ the
personal God freely reveals himself.
Obviously, if Schelling wishes
to represent the whole history
of
religion as the temporal represen-
tation
of
the divine life, it
is
very difficult for him to avoid asserting
a necessary connection between pagan mythology and Christianity.
The former would represent God as unconscious will, while the
latter would represent God as free
will,
the will of love. At the same
time Schelling tries to preserve an essential distinction between
mythology and revelation by insisting
that
the concept of revelation
is the concept of a free act on God's part. Revelation is the
truth
of mythology in
the
sense
that
it
is
that
at
which mythology aims
and
that
which underlies the exoteric clothing of myth. But
it
is in
and through
Christ
that
the
truth
is clearly revealed, and
it
is
revealed freely.
Its
truth
could not be known simply by logical
deduction from the pagan myths.
But though Schelling certainly tries to allow for a distinction
be~ween
mythology and revelation, there is a further important
pomt to make.
If
we
mean by revelation Christianity simply as a
fact which stands over against the fact of paganism, there is room
for a higher standpoint, namely
that
of reason understanding both
mythology and revelation. And this higher standpoint is positive
philosophy.
But
Schelling
is
careful to explain
that
he is not
referring to a rationalistic interpretation of religion from outside.
~e
is
referring to the activity
of
the religious consciousness whereby
It understands itself from within. The philosophy of religion
is
thus
for Schelling not only philosophy but also religion:
It
presupposes
Christianity and cannot exist without it.
It
arises within
Christianity, not outside it. 'Philosophical religion is therefore
historically mediated through revealed religion.'1
But
it cannot be
simply identified with
Christian belief and life as facts. For it takes
these facts as SUbject-matter for free reflective understanding.
In
con~r~st,
therefo:e, with the simple acceptance of the original
Chnsban revelabon on authority philosophical religion can be
ca1l~d.
rfr~e'
~e~gion.
:The
f~ee
religion
is
only
mediated
through
Chnsbaruty; It
IS
not lmmediately posited by
it.'!
But
this does not
mean
that
philosophical religion rejects revelation. Faith seeks
understanding;
but
understanding from within does not annul
what is understood.
This process of understanding, of free reflection, has its
own
1
W,
V,
p. 437.
•
w,
V, p. 440.