230
POST~KANTIAN
IDEALIST SYSTEMS
philosophy of absolute Spirit, as he expounds it, cannot abstract
from all temporal succession. And it has, therefore, two aspects.
It
may not indeed be always a simple matter to sort them out. But
in any case
we
only make nonsense of Hegel's doctrine if
we
take
him to mean, for example,
that
religion started only when
art
stopped. And whatever some writers may think
that
Hegel ought
to have said, in my opinion he looked on art, religion and philo-
sophy as permanent activities of the human spirit. He may have
thought
that
philosophy is the highest of these activities.
But
it
does not
follow
that
he imagined
that
man would ever become pure
thought.
By way of conclusion to this section
it
is worth drawing attention
to the following point.
It
is a mistake to think
that
according to
Hegel the State is the highest of all realities and
political~fe
~he
highest activity of man. For, as
we
have seen, the sphere
of
obJectlve
Spirit leads on to the sphere of absolute Spirit. And while organized
society in some form
is
for Hegel a condition for art, religion and
philosophy, these three activities are the highest expression
of
Spirit; Hegel doubtless exalted the State,
but
he exalted philosophy
still more.
2.
Dialectically or logically speaking, the Absolute
is
manifested
first of all in the form
of
immediacy, under the guise,
that
is
to say,
of objects of sense.
As
such, it is apprehended as beauty, which
is
'the sensuous semblance
[Scheinen]
of the Idea'.1 And this sensuous
appearance
of
the Idea, this shining of the Absolute
t~rough
~he
veils of sense, is called the Ideal. Looked
at
from one pomt
of
VIew
the Idea as beauty is, of course, identical with the Idea as truth.
For it is the same Absolute which is apprehended as beauty by the
aesthetic consciousness and as
truth
in philosophy. But the forms
or modes
of
apprehension are distinct. Aesthetic intuition and
philosophy are not the same thing. Hence the Idea as beauty
is
termed the Ideal.
While not denying
that
there can be such a thing as beauty in
Nature, Hegel insists
that
beauty in
art
is
far superior. For artistic
beauty is the immediate creation
of
Spirit; it
is
Spirit's manifesta-
tion of itself to itself. And Spirit and its products are superior to
Nature and its phenomena. Hegel confines his attention, therefore,
to beauty in art.
It
may indeed be regrettable
that
he
under~
estimates natural beauty as a manifestation
of
the divine. But,
1 W,
XU,
p.
160;
0,
I, p.
154.
In
references
to
Hegel's lectures on The Philosophy
0/
Fin.
A,./
the
letter
0 signifies
the
English translation
by
F. P. B. Osmaston.
HEGEL
(3)
given the construction of his system, he can hardly do anything else
but
concentrate on artistic beauty. For he has left the philosophy of
Nature behind him and
is
concerned with the philosophy of Spirit,
But,
we
may ask, if artistic beauty is said
to
be the sensuous
semblance or appearance
of
the Idea, what does this proposition
mean? Is it anything more than a high-sounding
but
vague state-
ment? The answer is fairly simple. The Idea is the unity of
subjectivity and objectivity. And in the beautiful work
of
art
this
unity
is
expressed
or
represented in the union of spiritual content
with external or material embodiment. Spirit and matter, subjec-
tivity and objectivity, are fused together in a harmonious unity
or
synthesis. f Art has the task of presenting the Idea to immediate
intuition in sensuous form, and not in the form of thought or pure
spirituality. And the value and dignity of this presentation lie in
the correspondence and unity of the two aspects of ideal content
and its embodiment, so
that
the perfection and excellence
of
art
and the conformity of its products with its essential concept
depend on the degree of inner harmony and unity with which the
ideal content and sensuous form are made to interpenetrate.'!
Obviously, Hegel does not mean to imply
that
the artist
is
consciously aware of the fact
that
his product is a manifestation
of the nature of the Absolute. Nor does he mean to imply
that
a
man
is
unable to appreciate the beauty of a work of
art
unless he
has this conscious awareness. Both the artist and the beholder may
feel
that
the product is,
so
to speak, just right or perfect, in the
sense
that
to add or subtract anything would be to impair or
disfigure the work
of
art. Both may
feel
that
spiritUal content and
sensuous embodiment are perfectly fused. And they may both
feel
that
the product is in some undefined sense a manifestation of
'truth'.
But
it
by no means
follows
that
either of them can state the
metaphysical significance
of
the work of art, whether to himself or
to anyone
else.
Nor does this indicate any defect in the aesthetic
consciousness. For
it
is
philosophy, and not the aesthetic conscious-
ness, which explicitly or reflectively apprehends the metaphysical
significance
of
art.
In
other words, this apprehension arises from
philosophical reflection
about art. And this is something very
different from artistic creation. A great artist may be a very
bad
philosopher or no philosopher
at
all. And a great philosopher
may
well be incapable
of
painting a beautiful picture or composing a
symphony.
1
W,
XII,
p.
IIO;
0,
I,
p. 98.