that it’s fair to say that any departure from it counts as a radical way of
thinking.
30
Nevertheless, ever since Aristotle there have been some phil-
osophers who are willing to be radical in this way. According to such phi-
losophers, events may be the only things that can be caused, but they are
not the only things that can be causes. For agents, too, according to this line
of thought, can also be causes. The idea is that when you move your hand,
for example, an event in your brain sends a signal to your muscles telling
them to move in the relevant way; and this brain event is not caused by
any other events; but the brain event nevertheless is caused; for it is caused
by something that is not an event – namely, you. Because the relevant
brain event is not caused by any other events, proponents of this view feel
that they are safe from the traditional Incompatibilist arguments against
freedom. And because the brain event in question is caused by you, propo-
nents of the view feel that they have an easy answer to the question of why
you should be responsible for the action that ensues.
There are two important presuppositions of libertarian Agent
Causation. First, the view presupposes that some events are like the brain
event described in the previous paragraph: they occur in the brains of
human agents; they are not caused by any previous events (and, hence,
they are not made physically necessary by previous events); and they result
in actions performed by the agents in whom they occur. (Note that this
first presupposition is one that libertarian Agent Causation shares with
the previous libertarian view we considered, Volitional Indeterminism.)
The second important presupposition of libertarian Agent Causation is
that agents are in a special category among things, insofar as they have
genuine causal powers.
31
In particular, the view presupposes that it is
and the view that the causal relata are states of affairs amount to the same thing. For
more on the question of what are the causal relata, see Chapter 2.
30
Not that we don’t have ways of talking that make it appear as if things other than
events can be causes and effects. (“The rock caused the window to break.” “Sarah
caused a commotion.” “The hurricane caused this mess.”) According to the trad-
itional way of thinking about causation, however, all such talk, when properly ana-
lyzed, turns out to be talk about causation between events. (“The rock hitting the
window caused the window to break.” “Sarah’s entrance caused a commotion.” “The
hurricane caused all of these things to come to be arranged in this messy way.”)
31
Here is the sense in which the causal powers of agents are said to be genuine. A rock
can “cause” a window to break by being caught up in an event – the throwing of
the rock through the window – that causes the window to break; and an agent can
do that, too. But in such cases, neither the rock nor the agent is really causing the