‘lawlike’ is introduced as a placeholder. It simply stands for that property
other than truth that a proposition must satisfy in order to be a law.
Within this framework, what is needed to give an account of lawhood is
an account of lawlikeness.
We stipulate regularity accounts to be versions of regularity that hold that
lawlikeness is an essential feature of every lawlike proposition. So, by defi-
nition, according to all regularity accounts, no matter how lawlikeness is
spelled out according to the account, if a proposition is lawlike in one pos-
sible world, it is also lawlike in all possible worlds. our reason for making
this stipulation is twofold. First, it does reflect an element of many early
attempts to give an account of lawhood. For example, it was – and still often
is – thought important that, in addition to being true, a law must (i) be
contingent and (ii) have a certain logical structure, and these two features
are usually thought to be essential features of propositions that have them.
Second, the stipulation lets us draw a fairly precise line between regular-
ity accounts and other accounts of lawhood. This will allow us to present
a criticism that challenges all regularity accounts at once. As we will see
soon, the assumption that lawlikeness is an essential feature of a proposi-
tion is problematic for certain subtle, but significant reasons.
We begin by focusing on a simplistic version of regularity that makes
lawlikeness a matter of being contingent and general: P is lawlike if and
only if P is a contingent generalization. This account does make some true
pronouncements. For example, it says that it is a law that no signals travel
faster than light. Still, the proposal faces at least three serious sorts of
problems. A careful look at these problems will give us a better appreci-
ation of how daunting the challenge is to understand better what it is to
be a law of nature.
First, there are many contingently true restricted generalizations that
are not laws. These generalizations are restricted in virtue of referring
to particular material objects. examples include the propositions that all
rocks in this box contain iron, that all the screws in Smith’s car are rusty,
and that all the apples in the refrigerator are yellow. Though these might
all be true, none of them is a law. even assuming they are all true, they
seem much too accidental. A piece of pure quartz in the box, a stainless
steel screw in Smith’s car, a ruby red in the refrigerator – these are all
things that readily could have been in place and each one, had it been in
place, would have made the corresponding generalization false. So, there