According to Simple Indeterminism, you are acting freely in this
example, since your action is undetermined, and you are also morally
responsible for your action.
27
But it doesn’t seem like you really are mor-
ally responsible for what you do in this case. After all, you did not try to
throw the ice cream back at the server; you did not know that you were
going to do that; and you did not even want to do that.
Here is a principle to bolster the claim that you are not morally respon-
sible for your action in this case:
Pure Chance
If an event is undetermined, then no one is responsible for that event.
The main idea behind Pure Chance is that when an event is undetermined,
its occurrence is like a cosmic roll of the dice. If the universe’s history
were rewound to a time just before that event and then allowed to unfold
again, with the same laws of nature and the same past, the undetermined
event might happen again, and it might not. And the factor that would
determine whether the event in question happened again, during the
replay, would be pure chance. In particular, no action by any agent would
be responsible for things going one way rather than another.
28
Notice that it won’t do at this point for the Simple Indeterminist to say
that in the ice cream example you are not morally responsible because you
neither tried nor wanted to do what you in fact did. For one thing, we often
take people to be morally responsible for accidentally behaving in certain
ways (as when someone carelessly causes a car accident, for example), even
though we know that the agents in question neither intend nor want to
do the things they do. And for another thing, there is simply no getting
around the fact that Simple Indeterminism, given the way it is stated, is
committed to you being responsible for your action in the ice cream case.
27
Assuming the story is told in a suitable way, that is, so that whatever other conditions
besides freedom are required for moral responsibility are also satisfied.
28
Perhaps it will be thought that a case like the following is a counterexample to Pure
Chance: Tim pushes a button to make it an indeterministic but very, very probable
matter that a certain bomb will go off, and the bomb then detonates. According to
the principle, Tim is not responsible for the explosion, but it seems like he really is.
A defender of Pure Chance can plausibly reply to this objection, however, by insist-
ing that what Tim is responsible for is pushing the button, which (given the circum-
stances) is a very bad thing to do, regardless of whether the bomb goes off or not.