idea of existence to his belief that it is composed
of two distinct parts. In the first part are those
things that exist simply because they are. They
exist “en-soi” or in themselves. Human beings,
however, belong to the second part, existing “pour-
soi” or for themselves. According to Sartre, the de-
marcation between the two parts of existence is
based on the fact that humans possess conscious-
ness, in particular an awareness of mortality; thus,
human beings exist in a constant state of dread.
Sartre’s premise, which he examines in later works,
was this: To give meaning to those things that exist
“en-soi,” it is necessary for humans first to detach
themselves from those things.
The importance of accepting responsibility for
one’s own actions is, therefore, also an essential
part of Sartre’s philosophy. His first dramatic
work, Les Mouches (The Flies, 1943), examines this
theme against the backdrop of ancient Greece,
using the mythological characters of Electra and
Orestes. Orestes, choosing to act by killing his
murderous mother, rejects the guilt that has para-
lyzed his city since Agamemnon’s death. His sec-
ond play, Huis-clos (No Exit, 1944), presents three
characters in a room with no way out, learning to
face the truth that “Hell is other people.”
Sartre also wrote works of literary criticism that
explore the responsibility of artists in relation to
their art, beginning with Qu’est-ce la Littérature?
(What Is Literature?, 1947). He followed this in the
same year with a study of
BAUDELAIRE, and in 1952
he published a biography of Jean GENET, Saint-
Genet, Comédien et Martyr (Saint Genet, Actor and
Martyr). Sartre admired Genet for being free of the
constraints of convention and making his own
personal distinctions between right and wrong.
Sartre was among a group of writers (including Al-
bert CAMUS and Jean COCTEAU) who in 1948 suc-
cessfully petitioned for Genet’s release from a life
sentence for burglary. From 1960 to 1971, he
worked on a massive critical biography of Gustave
FLAUBERT, L’Idiot de la famille (The Family Idiot).
The work reached five volumes but remained un-
finished, as in the last years of his life Sartre’s fail-
ing eyesight prevented him from writing.
In 1963, Sartre published his memoir of child-
hood, Les Mots (The Words), in which he explored
how language and literacy changed the conscious-
ness of the growing child. In that year, the Nobel
committee chose to honor Sartre with the Nobel
Prize in literature, but Sartre refused to accept the
award, feeling that it represented bourgeois values
he rejected. Nonetheless, his reputation continued
to grow, and his funeral drew thousands of
mourners.
Other Works by Jean-Paul Sartre
Colonialism and Neo-Colonialism. Translated by Steve
Brewer, Azzedine Haddour, and Terry McWilliams.
London: Routledge, 2001.
Notebook for an Ethics. Translated by Davis Pellauer.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992.
Truth and Existence. Translated by Adrian van den
Hoven. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1992.
Works about Jean-Paul Sartre
Gordon, Haim. Sartre’s Philosophy and the Challenge
of Education. Lewiston, N.Y.: E. Mellen Press,
2001.
Howells, Christina, ed. The Cambridge Companion to
Sartre. New York: Cambridge University Press,
1992.
Kamber, Richard. On Sartre. Belmont, Calif.:
Wadsworth/Thomson Learning, 2000.
McBride, William L., ed. Sartre’s Life, Times and Vi-
sion-du-Monde. New York: Garland Press, 1997.
Satyanarayana, Visvanatha (1895–1976)
poet, novelist, dramatist
Visvanatha Satyanarayana was born in Andhra
Pradesh, India. He wrote in Telugu and is the au-
thor of more than 100 works. This alone places
him among the most important figures in Telugu
fiction. He has also rewritten ancient Hindu epics
such as the The Ramayana, which dates from the
fourth century B.C. When his version of the epic,
Ramayana—The Celestial Tree appeared in 1953,
it was seen as controversial because of his transfor-
Satyanarayana, Visvanatha 389