R
HELLE LIEBER
n the literature, however, is whether these meanings are different and distinct, or
whether they are the same, with differe
es arising from the category and semantics
f the particular bases to which they attach. Marchand (1969) treats different
uances of meaning separately in each of
hese affixes, and Dowty (1979) argues in
ffect that negative and reversative
- are separate homophonous prefixes. Horn
1989/2001, 2002, forthcoming) and Lieber (2004) follow earlier work of Mayno
1979) and Andrews (1986) in ar
uin
that this cohort of affixes shares a central
ore of meanin
, with the extensive pol
sem
that the
displa
followin
from the
emantics of the base to which the
attach
I believe that a good case can be made for polysemy in this cohort of prefixes,
ather than homophony. Let us look first at the notion of negativity, which itself is
ot necessarily a unitary concept. As Horn (1989/2001) points out, we must
distinguish contradictory negation
r
contrary negation
In contradictories
omething is either X or not-X; the pos
tive and negative counterparts admit of no
iddle ground. For example something may be eithe
r
r
and
m
n
ith
on-pre
nan
, but there is nothin
in between. In
ontrast, someone ma
be neithe
app
n
unhapp
and a movie ma
be neithe
-
(at least for me). These latter negatives are contraries. In
terms of logic, contradictories obey the Law of the Excluded Middle
while
ontraries do not. In Lieber (2004) I argue that negative prefixes may deliver either a
ontradictory meaning or a contrary meaning, depending on the meaning of thei
base. Which interpretation arises depends on whether the base ad
ective can be
nterpreted as gradable or scalar. If a
ad
ective is amenab
e to a gradable
nterpretation (as happ
an
are for me), the resulting negative-prefixed form
will have a contrar
meanin
; if the ad
ective is not scalar or
radable in
nterpretation, the ne
ative-prefixed form will be interpreted as contradictor
. This
s true regardless of which negative prefi
we use. Speakers may of course differ on
which adjectives they feel to be gradable, and even whether a given adjective is
radable depending on nuances of meaning. For example, the adjective
r
i
on-gradable to me if it merely denotes
ationality: someone either holds American
itizenship or not. But to the extent that
m
n
’
ha
i
r
an
hara
t
riz
a
American’, that concept is
radable for me, and hence
-A
r
in that
n
as a contrar
rather than a contradictor
interpretation.
It has been noted in the literature
., Al
eo 1971, Horn 1989, 2001) that some
ad
ectives can be prefixed b
o
and
with the ne
ated ad
ective
aving slightly different nuances of meaning. When this occurs,
generally
argets a non-emotive or non-affective sense of the base, while
-
icks out a
ore emotion-laden sense. So, if we say that someone is
erely say that they do not work as a doctor, lawyer, professor, or the like. But if we
all th
nprofessional
we are accusing them of questionable conduct in the
workplace
Of the references mentioned, onl
Lieber (2004) treat
all
f th
affix
An
r
n
ntrat
n
an
and Horn on
-
an