
172 Physics in a curved spacetime
t
manifold, but the Euclidean space had its usual metric and time was measured by a
universal clock. Observers with different velocities were all equally valid: this form of rela-
tivity was built into Galilean mechanics. Therefore there was no universal standard of rest,
and different observers would have different definitions of whether two events occurring at
different times happened at the same location. But all observers would agree on simultane-
ity, on whether two events happened in the same time-slice or not. Thus the ‘separation in
time’ between two events meant the time elapsed between the two Euclidean slices con-
taining the two events. This was independent of the spatial locations of the events, so in
Newtonian gravity there was a universal notion of time: all observers, regardless of posi-
tion or motion, would agree on the elapsed time between two given events. Similarly, the
‘separation in space’ between two events meant the Euclidean distance between them. If
the events were simultaneous, occurring in the same Euclidean time-slice, then this was
simple to compute using the metric of that slice, and all observers would agree on it. If the
events happened at different times, each observer would take the location of the events in
their respective space slices and compute the Euclidean distance between them. The loca-
tions would differ for different observers, but again the distance between them would be
the same for all observers.
However, in Newtonian theory there was no way to combine the time and distance
measures: there was no invariant measure of the length of a general curve that changed
position and time as it went along. Without an invariant way of converting times to dis-
tances, this was not possible. What Einstein brought to relativity was the invariance of the
speed of light, which then permits a unification of time and space measures. Einstein’s
four-dimensional spacetime has a much simpler structure than Newton’s!
Now, within this model of spacetime, Newton gave a law for the behavior of objects
that experienced gravitational forces: F = ma, where F =−m∇φ for a given gravitational
field φ. And he also gave a law determining how φ is generated: ∇
2
= 4πGρ. These
two laws are the ones we must now find analogs for in our relativistic point of view on
spacetime. The second one will be dealt with in the next chapter. In this chapter, we ask
only how a given metric affects bodies in spacetime.
We have already discussed this for the simple case of particle motion. Since we know
that the ‘acceleration’ of a particle in a gravitational field is independent of its mass, we
can go to a freely falling frame in which nearby particles have no acceleration. This is
what we have identified as a locally inertial frame. Since freely falling particles have no
acceleration in that frame, they follow straight lines, at least locally. But straight lines in a
local inertial frame are, of course, the definition of geodesics in the full curved manifold.
So we have our first postulate on the way particles are affected by the metric:
(IV) Weak Equivalence Principle: Freely falling particles move on timelike geodesics
of the spacetime.
1
1
It is more common to define the WEP without reference to a curved spacetime, but just to say that all parti-
cles fall at the same rate in a gravitational field, independent of their mass and composition. But the Einstein
Equivalence Principle (Postulate
IV
) is normally taken to imply that gravity can be represented by spacetime
curvature, so we shall simply start with the assumption that we have a curved spacetime.