Was Pragmatism the Successor to Idealism? 165
understanding norms as instituted and as involving inference licenses
only raised the question of who-or-what authorized who-or-what to
perform such an act of instituting. Fichte famously concluded that it
could only be the ‘I’ (or the ‘absolute I’), which was itself to be seen
as a kind of Tathandlung, a ‘deed-act’, signifying the way in which
the semantical function of norms incorporates elements of both of
declarative and imperative sentences.²² The ‘I’ must simultaneously
both issue such inference licenses (such as ‘If A, then A’) and authorize
itself to issue such licenses. The ‘I’ as a subject of entitlement and
(epistemic and moral) responsibilities is thus not a natural thing, but it
is also not a supernatural or ‘unnatural’ thing. It is in fact not a thing in
the literal sense at all; it is a normative status.
The problem, as Fichte so clearly saw, was that if the story ended
there, there would be no account of any rational constraints on such
authorizations and licensings, such undertakings of commitments and
attributing of entitlements. For that, the subject of such undertakings
had to posit that there was something—famously, in Fichte’s obscure
jargon, a ‘Not-I’—that normatively constrained our acts, and by 1796,
Fichte was already attributing that function to another subject; such
individual subjects then constrained each other via acts of mutual
recognition. Indeed, only other subjects are capable, Fichte argued, of
normatively constraining the authorizations of each other as subjects in
acts of mutual attribution of responsibilities and entitlements.
In Hegel’s view, Fichte’s account still remained impossibly ‘subjective’
and ‘psychological’. We are ‘minded’ because we authorize ourselves,
which we accomplish in acts of mutual recognition; but this makes
our own status as ‘minded’ subjects dependent on the prior individual
attitudes that others take toward us. Although Fichte clearly came to
think that the process of self-authorization was social (and did not
come about through some miraculous act of an isolated ‘I’ positing
²² See Lance and O’Leary-Hawthorne 1997. That is, asserting a norm calls on the
agent to accept responsibility for the content of the norm, as is the case with a declarative
assertion; and it authorizes himself or another to act, as is the case with an imperative.
One of the differences has to do with the nature of imperatives; one cannot issue an
imperative to oneself, but one can impose, so it seems, a norm on oneself. This has to
do with the social nature of norms; norms can be imposed only to the extent that they
are collectively imposed. Individually imposed norms are only norms in an analogical
sense, in the same sense as when one says (in English), for example, that one ‘makes it a
rule’ to eat an apple every day. ‘Making it a rule’ imposes no norm on oneself, nothing
binding on oneself. (On this point of the impossibility of issuing imperatives to oneself,
my account of sociality departs from Lance’s and O’Leary-Hawthorne’s.)