Pragmatism and Ethical Particularism 133
advancing a suite of stable values. Thus Gouinlock claims that Dewey’s
is ‘a ‘‘principled’’ philosophy in that certain enduring values (such as
the democratic virtues) are proposed to guide conduct in all situations’
(Gouinlock 1994: p. xxv).
Dewey can, however, be read rather differently. In much of his work,
he writes primarily as a moralist who articulates and defends his cher-
ished ideals—of growth, intelligence, shared experience, democracy,
freedom—as part of an immanent critique of our moral ends, albeit
one that aims to throw our moral practices into relief by casting them as
activities of natural beings interacting with one another and the world.
Thus, it might be argued, Dewey does not delineate ends of moral
inquiry intelligible without the deployment of thick moral concepts,
for, as he himself puts it, ‘what sense is there in increased external control
except to increase the intrinsic significance of living?’ (Dewey 1976–83:
xiv. 183). Accordingly, his famous view of the reciprocality of means
and ends may be read not as a merely causal thesis, but as invoking the
Aristotelian idea of practices with internal goods, where the ends of a
practice are not intelligible independently of the perspective internal to
the practice itself and where the means deployed by those who engage
in the practice are partly constitutive of its ends (see MacIntyre 1981:
ch. 14). A sympathetic reader might, therefore, conclude that when
Dewey appears to look at morality sideways-on, he is simply in search
of critical distance from our practices in order to engage in the sort of
reflection upon them that McDowell describes as a constituent of free,
rational thinking. This is consistent with his seeing moral theory ‘as the
reflective clarification of practices that are already underway, or as a map
of the terrain of ethics for those already in it’, as Matthew Festenstein
perceptively characterizes Dewey’s project (1997: 26).¹¹
¹¹ Dewey’s writings do not make it easy to decide between the two readings. It is
important to note, however, that much that looks like a sideways-on account turns out,
on closer inspection, to be rather different. Consider the following passage:
The point at issue in a theory of educational value is then the unity or integrity of
experience. How shall it be full and varied without losing unity of spirit? How shall it
be one and not yet narrow and monotonous in its unity? Ultimately, the question of
values and a standard of values is the moral question of the organization of the interests
of life. Educationally, the question concerns that organization of schools, materials, and
methods which will operate to achieve breadth and richness of experience. How shall we
secure breadth of outlook without sacrificing efficiency of execution? How shall we secure
diversity of interests, without paying the price of isolation? How shall the individual be
rendered executive in his intelligence rather than at the cost of his intelligence? How shall
art, science, and politics reinforce one another in an enriched temper of mind instead of