84 Cheryl Misak
Peirce, that is, doesn’t need to learn the lesson Wright thinks he
has to teach the pragmatists: ‘For the purposes of pragmatism ...the
crucial reflection is that superassertibility is ...an internal property of
statements of a discourse’—a projection of the standards which actually
inform assertion within the discourse (2001: 781). Wright says that
the fact that ‘superassertibility is fashioned from our actual practices
of assessment’ makes it ‘well equipped to express the aspiration for a
developed pragmatist conception of truth as any other candidate known
to me’ (2001: 781). He is right to think that superassertibility is an
excellent candidate for a pragmatist conception of truth. What he fails
to see is that it is Peirce’s pragmatist account of truth.
There is, however, one significant difference between Wright’s view
and Peirce’s. Wright’s proposal is that we take as a truth predicate any
predicate which satisfies the DS and which takes truth to be distinct
from warranted assertibility. There may be more than one perfectly
good conception of truth.¹⁷ He thinks that superassertibility is the truth
predicate of choice for certain discourses—discourses in which we think
that if p is true, then p is knowable (1992: 58, 75; 2001: 779 f.). Other
discourses have more robust truth predicates.
Part of Wright’s project is a restructuring of the realist/anti-realist
debate. A discourse meeting only the minimal requirements for truth is
one about which we must take an anti-realist stance.¹⁸ The realist must
show that the discourse in question does more than meet the minimum.
There is a basis for making a distinction between claims about the comic
and claims about material objects, for a discourse can go beyond the
minimum. One way of doing this is for a discourse to display what
Wright calls cognitive command. Here it is a priori that intractable
disagreements are due to one kind or another of cognitive shortcoming,
such as insufficient or divergent evidence, faulty reasoning, inattention,
oversight, or malfunction of equipment.¹⁹
¹⁷ Wright 1992: 38. In his 1996 Wright does not foreclose on the possibility that
superassertibility holds everywhere—or at least, for every minimally truth-apt discourse.
If it turned out that Wright held the global thesis, one would have to see him
straightforwardly as a pragmatist. The global thesis, however, is in tension with the
direction of his argument in Wright 1992 and 2001.
¹⁸ Wright 1992: 142, 174. This is a striking claim, as it is often held that disquota-
tionalism captures, without mention of facts, states of affairs, and the like, the thought
at the heart of the correspondence theory.
¹⁹ Wright 1992: 90 ff., 175, 222. Another way of showing that a discourse goes
beyond the minimum is to show that the discourse is such that we detect matters rather
than matters being dependent on how we judge them. Another is to show that appeals