recognizing that S
¯
is an aggregate of the two types of uncertainty—nonspeci-
ficity and conflict—it must be that
(6.63)
where is a lower probability function, which can be derived from any of the
other representations of the same uncertainty (the associated convex set of
probability distributions, Möbius representation, or upper probability func-
tion) or may be converted to any of these representations as needed. In Eq.
(6.63) GH is the well-justified functional for measuring nonspecificity (defined
at the most general level by Eq. (6.38) and referred to as the generalized
Hartley measure) and GS is an unknown functional for measuring conflict
(referred to as the generalized Shannon entropy).
Since functionals S
¯
and GH in Eq. (6.63) are well justified and GS is an
unknown functional, it is suggestive to define GS from the equation as
(6.64)
Here, GS is defined indirectly, in terms of two well-justified functionals, thus
overcoming the unsuccessful attempts to define it directly (as discussed in
Section 6.5).
Functional S
¯
, which is well justified but practically useless due to its insen-
sitivity, can now be disaggregated into two components, GH and GS, which
measure two types of uncertainty that coexist in all uncertainty theories except
the classical ones. A disaggregated total uncertainty, TU, is thus defined as the
pair
(6.65)
where GH and GS are defined by Eqs. (6.38) and (6.64), respectively. Since
the sum of the two components of TU is S
¯
, TU is as well justified as S
¯
. One
advantage of the disaggregated total uncertainty, TU, in comparison with its
aggregated counterpart S
¯
, is that it expresses amounts of both types of uncer-
tainty (nonspecificity and conflict) explicitly, and consequently, it is highly sen-
sitive to changes in evidence.
Another advantage of TU is that its components, GH and GS, need not
satisfy all the mathematical requirements for measures of uncertainty. It
only matters that their aggregate measure, S
¯
, satisfies them. The lack of
subadditivity of GH for arbitrary convex sets of probability distributions,
established in Example 6.7, is thus of no consequence when GH is employed
as one component in TU.
EXAMPLE 6.15. To appreciate the difference between S
¯
and TU, let us
consider the following three bodies of evidence on X and let |X|=n for
convenience:
.