Paris and thus sparking oV the Trojan war. ‘She did what she did either
because of the whims of fortune, the decisions of the gods and the decrees of
necessity, or because she was abducted by force, or persuaded by speech, or
overwhelmed by love’ (DK 82 B11, 21–4). Gorgias goes through these
alternatives in turn, arguing in each case that Helen should be held free
from blame. No human can resist fate, and it is the abductor, not the
abductee, who merits blame. Thus far, Gorgias has an easy task: but in order
to show that Helen should not be blamed if she succumbed to persuasion,
he has to engage in an unconvincing, though no doubt congenial, enco-
mium on the powers of the spoken word: ‘it is a mighty overlord, insub-
stantial and imperceptible, but it can achieve divine eVects’. In this case, too,
it is the persuader, not the persuadee, who should be blamed. Finally, if
Helen fell in love, she is blameless: for love is either a god who cannot be
resisted or a mental illness which should excite our pity. This brief and witty
piece is the ancestor of many a philosophical discussion of freedom and
determinism, force majeure, incitement, and irresistible impulse.
Gorgias’ work entitled On What is Not contained arguments for three
sceptical conclusions: Wrst, that there is nothing; secondly, that if there is
anything it cannot be known; thirdly, that if anything can be known
it cannot be communicated by one person to another. This suite of
arguments has been handed down in two forms, once in the pseudo-
Aristotelian treatise On Melissus, and once by Sextus Empiricus.
The Wrst argument trades on the polymorphous nature of the Greek verb
‘to be’. I shall not spell out the argument here, but I shall endeavour in
Chapter 6 to sort out the crucial ambiguities involved. The second argu-
ment goes like this. Things that have being can only be objects of thought if
objects of thought are things that have being. But objects of thought are not
things that have being; otherwise everything one thinks would be the case.
But you can think of a man Xying or of a chariot driven over the sea without
there being any such things. Therefore, things that have being cannot be
objects of thought. The third argument, the most plausible of the three,
argues that each individual’s sensations are private and that all we can pass
on to our neighbours is words and not experiences.
The arguments of this famous sophist for these distressing conclusions
are indeed sophisms, and were no doubt dismissed as such by those who
Wrst encountered them. But it is easier to dismiss a sophism than to
diagnose its nature, and it is harder to still to Wnd its cure. The Wrst
PYTHAGORAS TO PLATO
31