Non-Marxian socialism 1815–1914
The phalange or phalanx was thus not to be communistic, nor was self-
interest to be abolished; hence Fourier’s principle of distribution is often
understood as more ‘realistic’ than that of the communist writers. (Accom-
modation and dining facilities of different grades were to be available too,
though ‘the food sent to the ordinary people’s kitchens’ would ‘be finer
than the food we reserve for kings’, Fourier 1996–8,p.164.) The economic
product was to be divided into three parts: capital receiving four-twelfths,
labour five-twelfths and talent three-twelfths (but individuals might belong
to each group). Freedom of inheritance would also secure existing fortunes.
But despite social classes, a spirit of unity would pervade the association: for
some it is thus ‘Fourier’s concept of community as individual self-realisation
through the creation of social institutions permitting human encounters
that defines him as a socialist’ (Poster, in Fourier 1971a, p. 20). The wealthy
would benefit by being no longer despised by the poor, and would assist in
some work purely for the sake of association. Hard labour would also be
better paid than pleasant work, with a generous minimum wage, each ‘Har-
monian’ being advanced clothing, food and housing each year, to be repaid
by labour (Fourier 1901,p.191). The government of the phalanx was to
be republican, with all officers elected, and coercion minimised. But details
of phalangist ‘politics’ are sparse; the assumption again is once the great
‘stumbling-block’ of politics, poverty, had been abolished (Fourier 1851,
i,p.339), fundamental divisions of opinion would not create entrenched
partisanship; that satisfied beings, content with, perhaps exhausted by, the
exercise of rich individuality, would be less prone to disagreement, and that
the passion for power over others, or the cabalist spirit of intrigue, would
have been sublimated by being channelled into the passional intrigues of
some thirty series.
3
By this means the rich, in particular, would be less prone
to desire domination over the poor in the phalange (Fourier 1971a, p. 299,
1851, i,pp.325–45,andii,pp.13–27, on cabalism). Eventually all phalanges
would federate and elect a single leader, resident at Constantinople. But this
would not be a paternalistic world-government, for Fourier was utterly dis-
missive of ‘the most ridiculous prejudice, the conviction that the good can
be established by government action’, claiming that every form of ‘civilised’
administration also preferred its own good (Fourier 1971a, p. 162).
3 ‘ . . . love, a passion of which the analysis appears ver y frivolous to us, and which, far from being a
spring foreign to the politics of harmony, will with ambition be then the most potent spring of the
industrial combinations, for in harmony love is quite as powerful a vehicle as ambition to attract men
to agricultural and manufacturing labor’ (Fourier 1851,vol.i,p.248). Fourier here calls love ‘a lever
of social politics’ (i,p.248).
535