FromJeremyBenthamtoJ.S.Mill
should proclaim it of themselves. But this is a matter of taste, and they are fond of calling
themselves by good names, and like ladies, seem glad to change them; so they have
been ‘philosophical Reformers,’ and ‘thorough Reformers,’ and ‘earnest Reformers’,
and better still, ‘entire Refor mers’. (Mill 1963, CWM, xiii,pp.369n–70n)
Mill was stung by this attack on him and on the journal. He protested that
the phrase, ‘philosophic radical’, was never bestowed by the journal on its
‘own writers or upon the people whom Bulwer called so in his speech’.
According to Mill, ‘philosophic radical’ was a name given ‘to the thinking
radicals generally’. He wanted to distinguish them from other radicals: ‘from
the demagogic radicals, such as Wakely, and from the historical radicals of
the Cartwright school, and from the division of property radicals if there
be any’. Mill had thought that the London and Westminster Review would be
the review representing ‘this large body’ and that the Examiner would be its
newspaper. But he particularly objected to his being classed with reformers
like Grote and Roebuck and pointed out that his radicalism was ‘of a school
the most remote from theirs, at all points, which exists’ (Mill 1963, CWM,
xiii,pp.369–70; see also Hansard’s Parliamentary Debates 1838, 3rd Series,
xl,pp.398–9; Thomas 1979,p.202).
Although Bentham would not have objected to Mill’s account of philo-
sophic radicalism in terms of ‘the common practice of philosophers’, Mill
had adopted a very different agenda from that found in Bentham and his
followers (see Kinzer 1991,pp.185ff.). Indeed, he wrote in the Autobiography
that he was pursuing two objects in the journal:
One was to free philosophic radicalism from the reproach of sectarian Benthamism. I
desired, while retaining the precision of expression, the definiteness of meaning, the
contempt of declamatory phrases and vague generalities, which were so honourably
characteristic both of Bentham and my father, to give a wider basis and a more free and
genial character to Radical speculations; to shew that there was a Radical philosophy,
better and more complete than Bentham’s, while recognizing and incorporating all of
Bentham’s which is permanently valuable. In this fir st object, I, to a certain extent,
succeeded. (Mill 1981, CWM, i, 221)
The second object was the attempt to reinvigorate radical politics, which
he admitted was for the most part a failure (Mill 1981, CWM, i,pp.221–3).
Mill’s belief in the practical success of his work in the London and West-
minster Review in freeing radicalism from the narrower confines of Ben-
thamism must be interpreted in conjunction with the essays on Bentham
and Coleridge which he published at the end of his involvement in the
review. But in the Autobiography Mill also distinguished between Bentham
279