
a predominant quality to be expected in a successful gene is ruthless
selfishness. This gene selfishness will usually give rise to selfishness in
individual behavior [. . .] there are special circumstances in which a gene
can achieve its own selfish goals best by fostering a limited form of
altruism at the level of individual animals. “Special” and “limited” are
important words in that last sentence. Much as we might wish to believe
otherwise, universal love and the welfare of the species as a whole are
concepts that simply do not make evolutionary sense.
30
As Clark describes Dawkins’ theory, “ ‘selfish genes’ do not allow for love,
for empathy, for being virtuous. Those are evolutionary no-no’s; they just
aren’t efficient. They decrease one’s fitness to survive.”
31
But it is difficult
indeed to explain the many altruistic actions we do observe in the real world—
the activities of rescuers such as Raoul Wallenberg and Per Anger, for
instance—if this is really how we are “wired” genetically. “I cannot see how we
could have evolved at all if we were constructed this way,” Clark argues.
“Indeed, I cannot see how any social mammals—the other primates, dolphins,
elephants—ever came into being following such rules of natural selection for
behavior.”
32
In particular, such a view fails to explain not only altruistic and
empathetic behavior in social life, but why we experience feelings of love and
grief and why we come together in groups at all. Instead of being shaped by
“selfish genes,” we are genetically predisposed or hard-wired to help other
human beings, Clark argues. In order for a species to continue to propagate
itself, it would certainly help enormously if that species were predisposed to
aid other members.
J. Philippe Rushton, on the other hand, argues that we can explain both
altruism towards our own ethnic groups and hostility towards others using
“genetic similarity theory,” the theory that we tend to favor those who are
genetically similar to us.
33
This kind of limited altruism evolved for evolutionary
purposes, since it tends to replicate our own genes. We tend to marry those
who are ethnically similar to ourselves, for instance, as well as similar in age,
education, attitudes, and even personality.
34
Analyses like these are highly
reductionist, however; though he disavows a purely genetic analysis of politics,
Ruston seems to view political attitudes as subconscious rationalizations for
genetic interests, a suggestion which leaves out a great deal.
35
This kind of
analysis does not really specify the mechanisms by which genetic impulses
become translated into political action, and also has difficulty explaining
hostility towards those who do not share our genetic makeup. Beyond stating
that “ethnic nationalism, xenophobia and genocide can become the ‘dark
side’ of altruism,” Rushton does not explain why genetics would lead to
outgroup hostility or the depth of such feelings.
36
The Psychology of Ethnic Conflict 177